Preamble
We the People of the United States, in Order to form a more perfect Union, establish Justice, insure domestic Tranquility, provide for the common defense, promote the general Welfare, and secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves and our Posterity, do ordain and establish this Constitution for the United States of America.
The Preamble was placed in the Constitution more or less as an afterthought. It was not proposed or discussed on the floor of the Constitutional Convention. Rather, Gouverneur Morris, a delegate from Pennsylvania, who as a member of the Committee of Style actually drafted the near-final text of the Constitution, composed it at the last moment. It is likely that the Committee assigned him to do so, inasmuch as such preambles were common practice in the era.
Nevertheless, it was Morris who gave the considered purposes of the Constitution coherent shape, and the Preamble was the capstone of his expository gift. The Preamble does not, in itself, have substantive legal meaning. The understanding at the time was that preambles are merely declaratory and are to be read as defining rather than granting or limiting power—a view sustained by the Supreme Court in Jacobson v. Massachusetts (1905).
The Preamble has considerable potency, however, by virtue of its specification of the purposes for which the Constitution exists. It identifies the legal power—the union—called into existence by the Constitution and distills the underlying values that moved the Framers during their long debates in Philadelphia. As Justice Joseph Story put it in his celebrated Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States (1833), “its true office is to expound the nature, and extent, and application of the powers actually conferred by the Constitution.” Alexander Hamilton, in The Federalist No. 84, went so far as to assert that the words “secure the blessings of liberty to ourselves and our posterity” were “a better recognition of popular rights than volumes of those aphorisms which make the principal figure in several of our State bills of rights.”
An appreciation of the Preamble begins with a comparison of it to its counterpart in the compact the Constitution replaced, the Articles of Confederation. There, the states joined in “a firm league of friendship with each other, for their common defence, security of their Liberties, and their mutual and general welfare” and bound themselves to assist one another “against all force offered to, or attacks made upon them, or any of them, on account of religion, sovereignty, trade, or any other pretence whatever.” The agreement was among states, not people, and the safety and liberties to be secured were the safety and liberties of the states.
The very opening words of the Constitution, “We the People of the United States,” presume the language of the Declaration of Independence, in which the “unanimous declaration of the thirteen united States” declared the sense of “one people.” It was therefore at striking variance with the prevailing norm, in that the word “people” had not been used in documents ranging from the Articles of Confederation drafted in 1777 and the 1778 treaty of alliance with France to the 1783 Treaty of Paris recognizing American independence, and the phrase “the United States” was followed by a listing of the states (“viz., New-Hampshire, Massachusetts-bay, Rhode-Island and Providence Plantations,” and so on down to Georgia).
The new phraseology was necessary, given the circumstances. The Constitutional Convention had provided that when the popularly elected ratifying conventions of nine states had approved the Constitution, it would go into effect for those nine, notwithstanding whether any of the remaining states ratified. Inasmuch as no one could know which states would and which would not ratify, the Convention could not list all thirteen. Moreover, states’ names could scarcely be added to the Preamble retroactively as they were admitted. Even so, the phraseology set off howls of protest from a number of opponents of ratification, notably Patrick Henry. Henry charged that the failure to follow the usual form indicated an intention to create a “consolidated” national government instead of the system that James Madison described in The Federalist No. 39 as being “neither a national nor a federal constitution, but a composition of both.” Henry’s assertion in the Virginia ratifying convention was promptly and devastatingly rebutted by Governor Edmund Randolph: “The government is for the people; and the misfortune was, that the people had no agency in the government before . . . If the government is to be binding on the people, are not the people the proper persons to examine its merits or defects?” Randolph made clear that the “people” and not the “states” acting through their established governments were the ratifying authority, a deliberate move on the part of the drafters of the Constitution. We should also note that George Washington’s “letter of transmittal" which reported the Convention’s work to the Confederation Congress specifically referred to the drafted “consolidation of our Union,” meaning that Henry spoke accurately but not quite to the point.
The Preamble’s first-mentioned purpose of the Constitution, “to form a more perfect Union,” was likewise subjected to misreading by Anti-Federalists. “More perfect” may strike modern readers as a solecism or as an ambiguous depiction, for “perfect” is now regarded as an absolute term. At the time of the Framing, however, it had no such connotation. For example, Sir William Blackstone, in his widely read Commentaries on the Laws of England, could assert that the constitution of England was perfect but steadily improving. Thus a more perfect union was simply a better and stronger one (one that is more perfected or brought to completion) than had pre-existed the Constitution. Yet a New York Anti-Federalist who wrote under the pseudonym Brutus professed to believe that, to carry out the mandate, it would be “necessary to abolish all inferior governments, and to give the general one compleat legislative, executive and judicial powers to every purpose.” Madison disposed of that exaggerated fear in The Federalist No. 46 by demonstrating that “the powers proposed to be lodged in the federal government, are as little formidable to those reserved to the individual States as they are indispensably necessary to accomplish the purposes of the Union; and that all those alarms which have been sounded of a meditated and consequential annihilation of the State governments must, on the most favourable interpretation, be ascribed to the chimerical fears of the authors of them.”
In the second stated objective, to “establish Justice,” the first word is “establish,” clearly implying that justice, unlike union, was previously nonexistent. On the face of it, that implication seems hyperbolic, for the American states and local governments had functioning court systems with independent judges, and trial by jury was the norm. But Gouverneur Morris chose the word carefully and meant what he wrote; he and many other Framers thought that the states had run amok and had trampled individual liberties in a variety of ways. The solution was twofold: establish an independent Supreme Court and, if Congress decided, a federal judiciary superior to those of the states and prohibit outright egregious state practices. Moreover, the third and fourth purposes presuppose justice, or just rule, as that for which security against domestic turmoil or foreign invasion is required.
The third avowed purpose, to “insure domestic Tranquility,” was in a general sense prompted by the longstanding habit of Americans to take up arms against unpopular government measures and was more immediately a response to Shays’ Rebellion in Massachusetts (1786–1787) and lesser uprisings in New Hampshire and Delaware. The most important constitutional provisions directed toward that end give Congress ultimate control over the militias (see Article I, Section 8) and guarantee each state a republican form of government and protection against domestic violence (see Article IV, Section 4). One should bear in mind that two rebellions broke out during the first decade under the Constitution, the Whiskey Rebellion (1794) and Fries’s Rebellion (1799), both of which were speedily crushed without the shedding of blood.
The fourth purpose, to “provide for the common defense,” is obvious—after all, it was by this means the United States came into being. But the matter cannot be dismissed lightly. For the better part of a century Americans had been possessed by a fear of “standing armies,” insisting that armed forces adequate to defend the nation would also be adequate to enslave it. Besides, ordinary Americans could believe that, since the War for Independence had been won over the best fighting force in Europe under the aegis of the Confederation, further provision was unnecessary as well as dangerous. Anti-Federalists clearly thought along those lines. By and large, those who agreed had seen little of the fighting during the war, whereas veterans of actual combat and people who had served in Congress or the administration during the darkest hours of the war knew differently. They expected that other wars would occur and were determined to be prepared to fight them. The Framers did, however, take fears of standing armies into account, hence their commitment to civilian control of things military, and, for many, the right to bear arms.
The fifth purpose, to “promote the general Welfare,” had a generally understood meaning at the time of the Constitution. The concept will be developed fully in the discussion of the Spending Clause of Article I, Section 8, but a few comments are germane here. The salient point is that its implications are negative, not positive—a limitation on power, not a grant of power. By definition “general” means applicable to the whole rather than to particular parts or special interests. A single example will illustrate the point. In the late 1790s Alexander Hamilton, an outspoken advocate of loose construction of the Constitution as well as of using the Necessary and Proper Clause to justify a wide range of “implied powers,” became convinced that a federally financed system of what would soon be called internal improvements—building roads, dredging rivers, digging canals—was in the national interest. But, since each project would be of immediate advantage only to the area where it was located, none could properly be regarded as being in the general welfare. Accordingly, Hamilton believed a constitutional amendment would be necessary if internal improvements were to be undertaken. James Madison, in his second term as president, would veto a congressional bill on precisely that ground.
The sixth purpose of the Constitution is to “secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves and our Posterity.” In broad terms the securing of liberty is a function of the whole Constitution; for the Constitution makes possible the establishment of a government of laws, and liberty without law is meaningless. Special provisions, however, in Article I, Sections 9 and 10 and in Article III were designed to prevent specific dangers to liberty about which history had warned the Framers. Those in Section 9 were drawn from the example of English history: the prohibitions against suspending the writ of habeas corpus, against bills of attainder and ex post facto laws, and against granting titles of nobility. In addition, Article III, Section 2,guaranteed trial by jury in criminal cases, andSection 3 defined treason extremely narrowly and prohibited corruption of the blood to protect innocent relatives from being punished. These are protections of individual liberty, not the liberty of states as under the Articles of Confederation. What the Preamble conveys is a clear sense that the purpose of this form of government entails certain consequences of liberty, and logically rejects consequences that are contradictions to liberty itself, such as the liberty to enslave others, a problem patently evident to many of the Framers themselves, but one which was abided so that the entire enterprise of republican government would not be derailed at its start.
To the extent that liberty confirms the right of consent for rational beings capable of choice, it depends for its continued existence as well as its efficacy on what James Wilson called the equal, honest, and impartial administration of the laws. The provision for the rule of law is crucial to curbing the excesses of liberty—a strengthening of liberty’s “blessings”—and therefore central in fostering moral virtue.
The restrictions in Article I, Section 10, apply to the state governments and were born of more recent history. The states are forbidden, among other things, to issue paper money, to make anything but gold and silver legal tender, or to pass bills of attainder, ex post facto laws, or laws impairing the obligation of contracts. All these mischievous kinds of laws had in fact been enacted by the states since the Declaration of Independence.
That brings us back to another point about the “general Welfare” and enables us to arrive at a broader understanding of the Preamble than is possible through a provision-by-provision analysis. Some historians have argued that the philosophy or ideology of the Constitution was at variance with that of the Declaration; indeed, several have described the adoption of the Constitution as a counter-Revolution. But consider this: the Declaration refers to God-given rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. The Preamble introduces a document whose stated purpose is to secure the rights of life and liberty. And what of happiness? Once again the word “Welfare” is crucial: in the eighteenth century the definition of welfare included well-being, but it also and equally encompassed happiness.
The Preamble as a whole, then, declares that the Constitution is designed to secure precisely the rights proclaimed in the Declaration. The Constitution was therefore not the negation of the Revolution; it was the Revolution’s fulfillment. What the Declaration sets forth as the reason for the people acting in the Revolution has been repeated in the Preamble as the end for which the people exist as a people. And this end, most notably, is promised not just to the people, but to “posterity.” In that sense, it emphatically endorses the transcendent moral purpose of both the Revolution and the move to “ordain and establish” the Constitution. The Preamble is far more a statement of the people’s duties than their hopes, duties by which they are honor bound to hold the government both politically and legally accountable.
Peter Charles Hoffer, For Ourselves and Our Posterity: The Preamble to the Federal Constitution in American History (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013).
Jacobson v. Massachusetts, 197 U.S. 11 (1905)