Introduction
No one committed to human rights denies what Article 3 of the Universal Declaration of Human RightsREF (UDHR) asserts: “Everyone has a right to life.” Rather, what is disputed today is the question of who is included under the term “everyone.” More than any other right, then, debates over the right to life implicate the basic scope of human rights protections, or, in the language of contemporary moral philosophy, the fundamental moral status of humanity and its individual members.
Core to these debates are three moral–legal categories: (1) the inherent dignity of members of the human family (referenced by the first and fifth preambular paragraphs of the UDHR, as well as by Articles 1 and 23REF); (2) equal rights consequent on the equal dignity of human beings (also referenced by the first and fifth preambular paragraphs, as well as by Articles 1 and 7REF); and (3) personhood (referenced by the fifth preambular paragraph, as well as by Articles 3 and 6).
Personhood and human dignity both indicate a unique kind of heightened moral status that requires human rights protections, while basic equality indicates that those with this status possess it equally and so are owed human rights protections equally, too. “Everyone” equally shares in personhood and human dignity and equally possesses human rights. This essay will return to the mutually reinforcing importance of these core categories for understanding who counts as “everyone” later on.
Natural Law
The immediate impetus behind the UDHR’s promulgation in 1948 was the injustices carried out before and during World War II, particularly those perpetrated by the National Socialist government of Germany. But far from originating with the UDHR’s drafters, the idea of what is meant by “human rights” hails from a long tradition of natural law reflection on justice.
Here it is important to be aware of the distinction between an idea or proposition and how its essence may be expressed in various formulations. While neither ancient Roman jurists nor Thomas Aquinas (A.D.1225–1274) possessed the precise idiom of “human rights,” they clearly understood and accepted its logically prior corollary: that justice requires giving to another what is his right (ius suum, with ius the root word for justice).REF So though a genuine development in the idiom of human rights occurred through Gratian’s seminal work of canon law (the Decretum, completed c. 1140) and the early commentaries it generated (up to c. 1200)—wherein a more subjectivized idea of ius as a power (potestas) or faculty (facultas) or liberty (libertas) of the individual was developedREF—this new idiom was but a particular articulation of ideas on justice endorsed by Aquinas and others before him in the natural law tradition.REF
What counts as right (and thus a right) within this tradition is settled by appeal to the natural law, i.e., the standard of the reasonable that is naturally inherent in human reflection on justice and morality. The Roman lawyer Ulpian (A.D. 170–223),REF Aquinas,REF and the early canon lawyersREF saw more clearly than their ancient Greek predecessors in the natural law tradition that everyone is by nature equal and thus due their natural right in virtue of their human nature (hence why natural law ethicists are equally comfortable with the terms “natural” and “human,” used as descriptions of fundamental rights).
Emerging out of the broad medieval natural law tradition, Francisco de Vitoria, Bartolome de Las Casas, and Francisco Suarez argued on behalf of the natural rights of native American Indians in the face of colonial exploitation in the 16th and 17th centuries.REF From this same moral and juridical lineage, Hugo Grotius appropriated the idea and idiom of natural rights and, in doing so, acted as the bridge over which natural rights were carried from the medieval canonists and post-Reformation second scholastics to modern protestant political theorists. The natural rights theories of Grotius, Samuel Pufendorf, Jean Jacques Burlamaqui, Christian Wolff, Emer de Vattel, and John LockeREF were, in turn, formative of the American Declaration of Independence of 1776, which, after mentioning the “Laws of Nature and Nature’s God,” declares: “We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness.”
The philosophy of natural rights was to the fore in that other important 18th-century precursor to the UDHR, the 1789 French Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen.REF The key drafter of the American Declaration, Thomas Jefferson, had a role in the drafting of the French Declaration, as it was he who advised the Marquis de Lafayette on the creation of the first model for the eventual 1789 Declaration.REF The final text of the French Declaration, influenced in part also by the Virginia Bill of Rights of 1776, invoked the “natural, inalienable, and sacred rights of man” and, “under the auspices of the Supreme Being” (Preamble), enumerated the “natural and imprescriptible rights of man” as “liberty, property, security, and resistance to oppression” (Article 2).REF
Universal Declaration of Human Rights
The drafters of the UDHR knew from where they were getting their ideas. One of the most influential framers of what was to become the preamble to the UDHR, René Cassin, looked to the preamble of the 1789 French Declaration for inspiration.REF Two of the most important template documents employed by the Canadian jurist John Humphrey in the composition of the very first draft of the UDHR, the “Pan American” declaration and a study sponsored by the American Law Institute, both drew heavily from the constitutional natural rights tradition.REF And when the UDHR was adopted in Autumn 1948, its drafters’ speeches made repeated reference to the 1776 and 1789 Declarations.REF
The overarching thrust of the natural law/natural rights tradition up to 1948 insisted upon human rights as rooted in human nature itself, so it is entirely fitting that the UDHR begins with the statement, “recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world” and goes on to reference “human beings” in the context of human rights protection, both in its second preambular paragraph and its very first article. The sufficient condition of being human for qualifying for human rights protection is what makes the insistence upon equal rights credible: Since no one shares more or less in human nature than any other human being, no one has a greater or lesser claim on human rights protection.
The UDHR’s invocation of dignity further illuminates the necessary and sufficient connection between human nature and possession of human rights. The very first draft preamble circulated was authored by John Humphrey and contained an alienable, extrinsic understanding of human dignity, “That there can be no human freedom or dignity unless war and the threat of war are abolished.”REF The second preamble circulated was authored by René Cassin and contained a much more intrinsic understanding of human dignity: “[H]uman freedom and dignity cannot be respected as long as war and the threat of war are not abolished.” The preambular statement that was eventually accepted was authored by Charles Malik, a Thomist philosopher and the leading philosophical influence on the UDHR’s drafting,REF and contained the phrases “inherent dignity” and “inalienable rights.”REF
Malik later explained the significance of these terms:
[T]he doctrine of natural law is woven at least into the intent of the Declaration. Thus it is not an accident that the very first substantive word in the text is the word “recognition”: “Whereas recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights, etc.” Now you can “recognize” only what must have been already there, and what is already there cannot, in the present context, be anything but what nature has placed there. Furthermore, dignity is qualified as being “inherent” to man, and his rights as being “inalienable,” and it is difficult to find in the English language better qualifications to exhibit the doctrine of the law of nature than these two.REF
During debates over Article 1, Eleanor Roosevelt (chairperson of the drafting commission) pointed out that dignity was included to emphasize that every human being is worthy of respect.REF Her remark was directed against the contention that dignity was not a right and therefore ought not to be part of any article of the UDHR. Roosevelt’s point was that human dignity explains why we have rights in the first place. Her position would later be attested to by both the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights which, in their second preambular paragraphs, affirm that human dignity founds human rights.REF
The intrinsic (“inherent”) account of dignity contained in the UDHR’s preamble coheres perfectly with the UDHR’s belonging to the natural rights tradition. Inherent dignity means that the categorical moral worth of individual human beings is intrinsic to (or rooted within) their nature as human beings. Hence, this dignity is properly human dignity. As such, the UDHR sets itself against all extrinsic accounts of dignity whereby an individual’s basic worth is contingent upon some property non-essential to his or her nature, such as those proffered by Thomas Hobbes,REF David Hume,REF and Friederich Nietzsche.REF
Instead, the UDHR aligns itself firmly in favor of easily the most influential account of dignity at the time of its drafting—the natural law account which was exemplified by, inter alia, Pope Leo XIII’s encyclical Rerum Novarum (1891), Pope Pius XI’s encyclical Quadragesimo Anno (1931), the preamble to the 1937 Irish Constitution (an overtly natural law constitution and the first ever to invoke individual dignity), Pope Pius XII’s 1942 Christmas Address,REF and the American Jewish Committee’s draft “Declaration of Human Rights” (1944).REF
The logically interdependent moral realities of human dignity and (equal) natural human rights cohere with the import of Article 6’s invocation of personhood, “Everyone has the right to recognition everywhere as a person before the law.” Personhood here is clearly understood in an inclusive sense: No one is to be excluded from being recognized as a person. In light of the positive references to “all human beings” (Article 1) and “all members of the human family” (first preambular paragraph), “everyone” in Article 6 ought to be interpreted as every human being. Johannes Morsink is correct to describe this as “stripped down” personhood,REF a conception of personhood stripped down to what Anna Grear terms the “embodied vulnerability of the human sub-stratum.”REF
There was considerable debate as to whether the reference to juridical personhood in Article 6 should be retained, with the U.K. and U.S. delegations particularly reluctant to keep it (for jurisprudential, and, possibly, in the case of the latter, domestic political reasons). However, the majority of delegates present were impressed by the arguments of Cassin and others who pointed out that personhood had been used as a legal tool for denying the fundamental rights of human beings, such as Jews and African Americans. The article was necessary according to Cassin because “persons existed who had no legal personality.”REF Recognizing personhood as inclusive of all individuals who share in a common rational nature, like human nature, is a feature of the natural law tradition.REF
The contrary view is that of an exclusive account of personhood that divorces personhood from human nature and makes of it an exclusive, elite status higher than the status of simply being human.REF But the exclusive account was alien to human rights thinking at the time of the UDHR’s drafting; the dominant view was the inclusive understanding, as present within the U.S. Catholic Bishops’ draft “A Declaration of Rights” (1946), the American Jewish Committee’s draft “Declaration of Human Rights” (1944), and the American Declaration of the Rights and Duties of Man (1948).REF
The incorporation of an inclusive account of personhood in the UDHR is perfectly appropriate because inclusive personhood perfectly coheres with intrinsic dignity. Common employment of the categories “dignity and personhood” in contemporary moral philosophy indicates that they are interchangeable, which is how they operate in the UDHR, too. There, they both signify the unique, fundamental moral worth of the individual qua human being.REF And this is precisely how contemporary natural law scholars understand the interrelationship between these two categories:
Although there are different types of dignity, in each case the word refers to a property or properties—different ones in different circumstances—that cause one to excel, and thus elicit or merit respect from others. Our focus will be on the dignity of a person or personal dignity. The dignity of a person is that whereby a person excels other beings, especially other animals, and merits respect or consideration from other persons…what distinguishes human beings from other animals, what makes human beings persons rather than things, is their rational nature.REF
It was this last point that Malik intended to make by his insistence on including the clause “endowed with reason and conscience” in Article 1.REF Not only are the affirmations of inclusive personhood and inherent dignity by the UDHR consistent, they help make credible the claim that all members of the human family have equal human rights.
The Right to Life of Unborn Children
The UDHR’s reliance on the mutually illuminating and mutually dependent categories of equal human (natural) rights, inherent human dignity, and inclusive personhood means that it endorses human rights as belonging to human beings by virtue of their human nature. This itself entails that the deep logic (as well as prima facie meaning) of the UDHR requires recognizing that members of the human family living in utero possess human rights, and thus the right to life.
The right to life is centrally the right against being intentionally killed. It has dual application: horizontal (against the activities of other persons) and vertical (against activities of the state). The moral norm underpinning the right to life is exceptionless (“absolute”) in the sense that once it is specified adequately (i.e., no intentionalREF killing), the right does not permit of further qualification, limitation, or “balancing.”REF
The right to life most certainly excludes all utilitarian attempts to justify the intended killing of innocents on the basis that such killings supposedly effect an overall net good when compared to the effects of the choice not to perpetrate them. The utilitarian view sees one course of action as more moral than another when it more fully instantiates (the most plausible version of) the principle of “the greatest good for the greatest number.” Utilitarianism permits what, in reality, is immoral and contrary to respect for human rights partly because it fails to acknowledge human dignity.
As a uniquely supreme kind of worth, human dignity is priceless and incommensurable—there is no metric according to which it can be measured, calculated, and compared, even as regards other of its instantiations in human persons.REF So it is rationally senseless to claim that furthering the interests of a majority can morally “outweigh” a violation of human dignity brought about through the intentional killing of an innocent or innocents.REF
And yet many legal and other scholars argue that abortion, the intentional killing of an unborn human being, is a human right. What is more, they appeal to the UDHR in so arguing. Their line of reasoning centers of the inclusion of the term “born” in Article 1 and is typified by the claim of Christina Zampas and Jaime M. Gher that “the term ‘born’ was intentionally used to exclude the [fetus] or any other antenatal application of human rights.”REF Zampas and Gher argue that a proposal was made to delete the term “born” precisely on the basis that it seemed to exclude the unborn from human rights recognition, and that this proposal was rejected.
Similarly, Rhonda Copelon, Zampas, Elizabeth Brusie, and Jacqueline deVore argue that a remark by the French delegate during drafting to the effect that the right to freedom and equality is “inherent from the moment of birth” was directed against a proposed amendment to delete the term “born,” an amendment motivated by a concern to include unborn human beings within the ambit of human rights protection.REF Therefore, they conclude, the term “born” in Article 1 counts against human rights protections for the unborn.
In fact, the converse is the case. Johannes Morsink demonstrates in his study into the origins of the UDHR that debates over the retention or rejection of the term “born” did not center on the question of abortion or the moral status of fetal life, but on whether human rights are inherent within human nature or, instead, are attributed to human beings from some source extrinsic to their very existence, such as society or law.REF The contention by the French delegate that the right to freedom and equality is “inherent from the moment of birth” was directed against not a pro-life proposal but the Soviet position, whereby equality of rights before the law is “determined not by the fact of birth, but by the social structure of the state.”REF
The insertion of the term “born” in the first place was at the behest of a joint French and Philippine proposal.REF It echoed Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s The Social ContractREF and Article 1 of the 1789 French Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen, which Rousseau helped inspire (“Men are born and remain free and equal in rights”), which themselves echoed the Ulpian’s proposition included near the beginning of Justinian’s Digest of the 6th century, “by natural law all were born free.”REF Rousseau’s moral opposition to abortionREF indicates that he had no difficulty employing “born” as a signifier without implying that the value of “humanity” has no pre-natal application. Neither did the Digest, which affirms the civil rights of unborn children.REF And neither did René Cassin of France, the co-proposer of the amendment that included the term “born,”REF nor the Chilean delegate, Hernán Santa Cruz, who spoke in favor of the philosophy underpinning the term.REF Both delegates stated their moral support for the human rights status of unborn human beings during the course of the UDHR’s drafting.REF
So while it is true that by dint of a philosophical misunderstanding, a few delegates (those of Mexico and Venezuela) objected to the term “born” on the grounds that it could imply disregard for the unborn child,REF these objections were extraneous to the real import of what “born” signified. What it signified then—as now—is that human rights and human dignity inhere (are intrinsic to) human nature as per the moral relevance of that nature. Dignity and rights cannot inhere in human nature if they are contingent upon the materialization of developed or immediately exercisable (as distinct from latent or root) capacities proper to paradigmatic (healthy, mature, non-disabled) members of the human family. As such the intended meaning of the disputed qualifier counts in favor of unborn human rights.
Further support for this contention is that no delegate argued in favor of retaining the term “born” on the basis that it meant that only actual physically born human beings could claim human rights. The argument in favor of retaining the term was based exclusively on support for the view that both equal dignity and human rights are inherent in all human beings. (As Article 2 puts it: “Everyone…without distinction of any kind.”) Malik, typically, was acutely aware of the true significance of this debate: “[T]he word ‘born’ means that our freedom, dignity and rights are natural to our being and are not the generous grant of some external power.”REF
Does the UDHR, then, affirm the rights of all human beings, including unborn human beings? The matter does not, to my mind, permit a univocal, unqualified judgment. Proposals were, in fact, made to explicitly include the unborn within the terms of Article 3 (which at the time was draft Article 4), which enumerates the right to life. One such proposal was made by the Chilean delegate and stated, “unborn children, incurables, the feeble[-]minded [sic] and the insane have the right to life.”REF This suggestion would be discussed alongside a recommendation by Malik, “Everyone has the right to life and physical integrity from the moment of conception regardless of his or her physical or mental condition. Everyone has the right to liberty and personal safety.”REF Both proposals were rejected.
Two reasons were advanced against their adoption: the need for concision within the UDHRREF and the fact that not all countries prohibited abortion in all circumstances.REF No delegate argued that unborn children were not entitled to human rights protection per se. For instance, Cassin took a stand against Malik’s proposal on the basis that it was not acceptable to every member, while also expressing his agreement with the proposal’s substance.REF Malik is also reported as requesting:
[T]hat reference should be made in the summary record of the meeting to the statements made by the representatives of China, the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, and the United Kingdom in connection with [the then] article 4…. [W]hile the delegations of those three countries wished to omit the phrase “from the moment of conception” in the interests of brevity, they considered that idea to be implied in the general terms of article 4.REF
In response to Malik’s request, the Chinese delegate stressed that the wording of the draft Article not only implied but actually contained the idea expressed by Malik’s amendment;REF the United Kingdom delegate stated that Article 4 could be understood to contain such an idea but did not necessarily do so.REF The proposals to include “from the moment of conception” and “regardless of his or her physical or mental condition” were each voted on separately and were each defeated six votes to two.REF
The proposal to explicitly protect unborn children was rejected for the sake of succinctness and generality, and because its inclusion may have proved an obstacle to some states signing the UDHR. No argument was made against the proposal to the effect that the unborn child does not possess human rights as such, and no argument was made to the effect that there is a human right to abortion. (Indeed, no attempt was ever made during the drafting of the UDHR to include even a heavily limited right to abortion.) Thus, out of the two distinct positions put forward on the issue, one explicitly argued that the unborn child possessed human rights, while the other position, which was officially endorsed, was an admixture of stylistic and sovereignty concerns. Out of the six votes against the proposal, two were clearly motivated by stylistic concerns (the votes of the United States and China), and three were primarily motivated by sovereignty concerns (the votes of the United Kingdom, the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, and France). The travaux préparatoires shed no light on the intention behind the Australian vote. If it was motivated by a desire for concision, an approach urged by the Chairperson just prior to the vote,REF then an evenly split intention between stylistic and sovereignty concerns would have formed the successful vote. At worst, therefore, the vote against the proposal was intended to make it easier for certain states to sign on to the UDHR. There was no principled, morally substantive opposition to unborn human rights or support for abortion rights.
Perhaps the best summation of the UDHR on the matter, when all relevant preambular paragraphs, articles, and debates are taken into consideration, including the most philosophically and historically attentive interpretation of the core terms inherent in each, is:
- Yes, the UDHR offers substantive moral support for the recognition of the human rights of unborn human beings as members of the human family;
- No, the UDHR does not explicitly include unborn children under its right to life; and
- No, the UDHR neither affirms a human right to abortion nor offers substantive moral support for a human right to abortion.
The UDHR’s relationship to the human rights status of the unborn child is in some ways similar to the relationship between the original U.S. Constitution (inclusive of the Bill of Rights) and the human rights status of African Americans. Presupposing the overtly natural rights philosophy of the Declaration of Independence, the Constitution enumerated various natural rights and gave its endorsement to the fundamental, natural equality of all human beings.REF Yet this endorsement was importantly deficient since the Constitution’s protection of African Americans’ natural rights was insufficiently explicit given the threatening cultural context facing them, and was even undermined by provisions like Article IV, section 2, clause 3.REF Similarly as regards the Declaration itself, the decision to omit Jefferson’s words against the King waging “cruel war against human nature itself” through royal support for the slave trade injured the humane tenor of the document (and was a decision made at the behest of southern opposition, and thus—as with the UDHR drafting decision to omit explicit reference of the unborn under the right to life—motivated by sovereignty and consensus concerns).
So despite these founding documents’ natural rights underpinnings, they were ill-equipped to remove the legal possibility of a future Supreme Court decision like Dredd Scott v. Sanford, which harnessed cultural prejudices to reject the fundamental equality of African Americans and their natural right not to be held in slavery as the possession of another. The Dredd Scott majority construed the Constitution against the grain of its moral and philosophical underpinnings and held that colored people are “a subordinate and inferior class of beings”REF who “had no rights or privileges but such as those who held the power and the Government might choose to grant them.”REF
And yet the inherent natural rights logic of both the Constitution and the Declaration of Independence was irrepressible. The dissent in Dred Scott spoke to it: “A slave is not mere chattel. He bears the impress of his Maker, and is amenable to the laws of God and man; and he is destined to an endless existence,”REF and “slavery, being contrary to natural right, is created only by municipal law.”REF Dissent was assented to during Congressional debates over the Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amendments, wherein appeal to the natural, inalienable, equal rights of human beings was ubiquitous.REF
Since then, there have been legally endorsed setbacks on the road to the proper recognition of the human dignity of all regardless of such accidental characteristics as skin color, not least Plessy v. Ferguson,REF but when they have been overcome, it has been through (as Martin Luther King Jr. famously put it) living out the true meaning of the creed: “We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal.”
In a similar way the UDHR’s affirmation of inherent human dignity, equal human rights, and inclusive personhood is oriented firmly toward a more explicit recognition of the human rights status of the unborn. Like the Reconstruction Amendments and the Civil Rights Act, a day may come when this more explicit recognition fully materializes in human rights law, even if the materialization must occur against the grain of the views of bodies tasked with operating faithfully according to the meaning of the UDHR.
Subsequent International Human Rights Law
Subsequent international human rights law has in fact provided more explicit—if still not fully explicit—recognition of the unborn child’s human rights. Article 6(5) of the 1966 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights protects the right to life of unborn children whose mothers have been sentenced to death. (“Sentence of death…shall not be carried out on pregnant women.”) The travaux show the provision was added out of consideration for “the interests of the unborn child.”REF
This section proceeds from and is intelligible in light of Article 6(1), “Every human being has the inherent right to life. This right shall be protected by law. No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of his life.” As with the UDHR drafting, an unsuccessful attempt was made to explicitly include reference to the unborn under Article 6(1). A proposed amendment to insert the clause “from the moment of conception” into the right-to-life article was defeated by 31 votes to 20 (with 17 abstentions).REF But the travaux make it clear that the vote was not lost due to a direct rejection of the idea that unborn children possess human rights or due to any notion that there is such a thing as a human right to abortion. Rather, delegates were concerned with the lack of legal clarity arising from the invocation of conception as a legal marker and, to a seemingly lesser extent, with the need to respect state sovereignty in light of the incompatibility of the amendment with extant abortion legislation in various jurisdictions.
The 1966 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR) did not discuss the right to life of unborn children in the context of the abortion controversy. It did, however, recognize that the unborn child requires human rights protection in the child-centric Article 12(2)(a). In the context of ensuring that “everyone” enjoys the highest standard of physical and mental health, the ICESCR holds that “steps to be taken by the State Parties to the present Convention…shall include…the provision for the reduction of the stillbirth-rate and of infant mortality and for the healthy development of the child.”
The 1959 United Nations Declaration on the Rights of the Child had, by this stage, already indicated that “child” includes the child “before as well as after birth.” And the inclusion of this statement in the third preambular paragraph of the 1989 U.N. Convention on the Rights of the Child (UNCRC) forms what remains the most explicit affirmation of the human rights status of the unborn child by international human rights “hard” law: “[T]he child, by reason of his physical and mental immaturity, needs special safeguards and care, including appropriate legal protection, before as well as after birth.”
Though appearing to be an entirely unambiguous affirmation of the human rights status of the unborn child, the significance of the UNCRC’s preambular statement is qualified by the placement in the travaux “on behalf of the entire Working Group” the following statement, “[I]n adopting this preambular paragraph, the Working Group does not intend to prejudice the interpretation of article 1 or any other provision of the Convention by State parties.”REF This interpretative statement itself would be the subject of a legal opinion from the U.N.’s Legal Counsel, an opinion furnished after the Working Group had completed its work and that cast significant doubt on the legal effect of the interpretative statement.REF
A point the opinion intimates is that in international law hermeneutics (as per Articles 31 and 32 of the 1969 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, or VCLT),REF the ordinary meaning of the preamble ranks higher than appeal to supplementary means of interpretation such as the travaux. Despite an element of ambiguity over its precise significance in international human rights law, then, the UNCRC’s preamble remains a more explicit and more general affirmation of the unborn child’s human rights than hitherto achieved. It is also part of a trend that is both clear and clearly faithful to the moral–philosophical foundations of the UDHR.
In the 1990s, another trend began pertaining to the status of the unborn in intentional human rights law. Of itself, this particular trend did not amount to a development of international human rights law but rather involved a radical shift in how United Nations bodies interpreted this law. So seemingly from nowhere and without offering anything like a reasoned justification the Human Rights Committee (HRC), a body established pursuant to Article 28 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), began declaring that compliance with the ICCPR requires the decriminalization of abortion in cases of “rape, incest, serious risks to the health of the mother, [and] fatal fetal abnormality.”REF
The HRC now also expresses concern at the “discriminatory impact” of abortion laws that criminalize most abortions within a jurisdiction and thus prevent women of lesser economic means (who cannot afford to travel) from procuring an abortion.REF The body routinely challenges states with restrictive abortion laws and does so primarily by appeal to Articles 3,REF 6,REF and 7REF of the ICCPR.
In its recent General Comment (No. 36) on Article 6, the HRC construes that article to effectively contain a near-unlimited right to abortion.REF No effort is made by the HRC to offer anything like a ratio decidendi for rejecting the applicability of human rights to unborn children and for incorporating a right to abortion into the text of the ICCPR. The manifold “concluding observations” and “general comments” simply assert the existence of a right to abortion under that instrument.
Despite presentations, suggestions, and posturings to the contrary, the HRC’s “concluding observations” and “general comments” do not form part of binding international human rights law. The same goes for all U.N. treaty-monitoring bodies. This is something that even scholars very sympathetic to the activities of treaty-monitoring bodies accept.REF The HRC is not a judicial-type body and does not have the legal power to develop, delete, or add to the ICCPR’s provisions, as is clear from the text of the ICCPR itself.
Article 40(1) provides for states party to the Covenant “to submit reports [to the HRC] on measures they have adopted which give effect to the rights recognized herein [i.e., in the ICCPR itself],” while Article 40(4) requires the HRC to transmit reports and general comments to the state parties. Since this is the extent of the HRC’s powers under the ICCPR, it acts ultra vires when it seeks to alter, add to, or diminish the rights recognized by the ICCPR or to otherwise amend that instrument.
The problematic nature of the HRC’s approach to the human rights of the unborn child is mirrored in most other U.N. treaty-monitoring bodies. The Committee on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW Committee),REF established pursuant to Article 17 of the 1979 Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW), is perhaps the most insistent on a human right to abortion. The CEDAW Committee regularly appeals to Article 12(1) of CEDAW to support abortion rights. (“States Parties shall take all appropriate measures to eliminate discrimination against women in the field of health care in order to ensure, on a basis of equality of men and women, access to health care services, including those related to family planning.”)
Yet, like the ICCPR, the CEDAW makes no provision for abortion as a human right, either in Article 12(1) or elsewhere. This is ascertainable from a good faith reading of its actual textual provisions and confirmed by its travaux (which indicate that abortion was not understood as a human right component of “family planning” or any other CEDAW provision).REF Constitutional scholars of almost every generation and nationality are familiar with a glaring disjunction between the underlying philosophy of a foundational legal text and an aspect of its current official interpretation. So it is with the current incompatibility between, on the one hand, the underlying moral philosophy of the UDHR—reflected in its explicit text—and the instruments promulgated pursuant to it, and, on the other, the free-floating interpretations of these human rights documents asserted by U.N. treaty-monitoring bodies, which somehow infer a right to abortion.
Disintegration of the Human Rights Philosophy
In the minds of many human rights scholars today, debates over the human rights status of unborn children are rather peripheral to the future of human rights. At most, they tend to assume that the status of the unborn matters really only insofar as it impacts upon the discrete matter of the right to abortion. (What matters for a clear majority of scholars is that the status of the unborn is resolved in such a way as to leave the right to abortion intact.) Very few think that the credibility of human rights as a whole stands or falls on the status of unborn children, and so very few are in the least bit troubled by how U.N. treaty-monitoring bodies implicitly—yet really—disparage the human rights status of unborn children.
But the basic credibility of human rights as a whole is at stake in these debates. This is not a circular claim; its veracity can be apprehended by appreciating diverse-yet-intertwined insights from a variety of philosophical sub-disciplines, something most human rights scholars and members of treaty-monitoring bodies are not readily in a position to do. These insights have enormous implications for human rights, though, and it is imperative to consider them.
Honest and scientifically informed thinkers in favor of abortion rights know that the unborn entity is a human being.REF Usually, too, they subscribe to at least some vestigial respect for the idea that it is intrinsically wrong to kill innocent persons. The obvious solution to the dilemma is to deny that unborn human beings are moral persons (or, what is essentially the same thing, possess equal human dignity). For the denial to be minimally plausible, of course, it must appeal to a criterion of moral personhood (or of possessing human dignity) the unborn fail to satisfy. The standard of personhood that quickly became the dominant, consensus position was that of having the immediately exercisable (as distinct from latent or root) capacity for self-consciousness.REF
It was a position alien to the thought of the most influential fathers of the natural rights tradition when they considered personhood in the context of justice and rights.REF These philosophers assumed that to possess human nature was to be a person. Theirs was an intrinsic, inclusive account of personhood. The revisionist account, on the other hand, posited personhood as contingent upon the experiencing of an advanced developmental stage wherein a relevant root capacity develops into a corresponding, immediately exercisable capacity. The root capacity that makes possible an immediately exercisable capacity is itself intrinsic to human nature and, thus, the immediately exercisable capacity is contingent upon an intrinsic feature of human nature. But the immediately exercisable capacity considered in isolation is, strictly speaking, non-essential to human nature and thus in that way extrinsic to it.
As extrinsic to human nature, the revisionist account of personhood excludes various human beings. This, of course, was the point. But even philosophers in favor of abortion quickly came to realize that it was not just unborn human beings who were excluded by this revisionist standard. Michael Tooley illustrated clearly in his seminal 1983 work, Abortion and Infanticide, published just 20 or so years after the legislative push for abortion rights fully kicked into gear, that newborn human beings were similarly “non-persons” according to the revisionist standard of personhood.REF It was a simple matter of logical consistency.
Peter Singer’s work helped popularize the argument Tooley was making, and today it is widely accepted among bioethicists that infanticide, in effect, the intentional killing of newborns, is substantially equivalent to the killing of children pre-birth in the sense that none of the beings killed are persons (only persons have a proper right to life).REF The practical implications of this concession have been much less acute than the practical implications of the social consensus concerning abortion, though largely because the latter removes almostREF all practical relevance from the former.
At the other ends of life’s spectrum, that same revisionist standard of personhood has engendered a broad bioethical consensus in favor of the allegedly sub-personal nature of human beings who are alive but lacking any significant level of consciousness as a result of acquired, severe cerebral impairment (as occurs in cases of injury resulting in a so-called persistent vegetative state, or PVS).REF Law in certain influential jurisdictions has followed suit and permits the “letting die” (in reality: deliberate killing via act or omission) of such profoundly impaired human beings since it is supposedly in their “best interests” to die.REF (This rationale for legalized killing is tantamount to holding that a human being’s life in a PVS-like condition is sub-personal and that therefore they themselves are not fully a person and do not possess equal human dignity.)
It did not take long for the rejection of inclusive personhood that predicated these sorts of decisions to trickle down into decisions to euthanize incompetent, non-PVS patients (e.g., those with severe dementia or in a coma) without their explicit request. And so non-voluntary euthanasia is often unofficially tolerated to the point of quasi-formal policy in jurisdictions like Belgium and the Netherlands.REF All this is relatively well-known in moral philosophy and medical law.
What is much less well-known publicly is that a small number of serious philosophers have in the past 15 years or so applied the revisionist account of personhood to cases of adults with profound intellectual disabilities. Inevitably, the results have been troubling. The possession by an individual of a profound intellectual disability often entails his lacking a sufficiently robust ability for self-consciousness to satisfy the revisionist criterion for personhood.REF The implication, not always unstated, is that these persons do not possess a right to life.
It is noteworthy that some of the most vehement opposition to this development comes from secular feminist ethicists. How do they argue against the de-personalizing of the profoundly intellectually disabled? Often by appealing to the unique worth of both human nature and natural, biological relationships between dependent human beings.REF
Although it is abundantly clear to most serious scholars working on the interrelationship between bioethics and moral status that the revisionist account of personhood renders many more categories of human beings non-persons beyond unborn children, human rights and other legal scholars who embrace the revisionist account for the purposes of abortion advocacy seem largely uninformed of this implication—or at least very rarely advert to it publicly. The wider implications of their account of personhood should trouble them massively, and yet they remain seemingly unperturbed.
The matter is even more problematic than that of human rights abandoning some of the most vulnerable categories of human beings and leaving them outside the scope of human rights protection. A further entailment of the revisionist account of personhood is only beginning to appear on the radar of moral philosophers. It can be appreciated by combining the aforementioned insights from the fields of bioethics and moral status with important insights from the field of value theory.
The divorce of personhood from human nature turns out to unravel human rights in its entirety. How? To begin with, a credible account of revisionist personhood cannot rely on magic. In other words, it cannot suppose that in the order of human development a human at point p is simply a non-person and at the very next developmental point, p + 1, is fully a person. Cognitive science rejects the idea that the immediately exercisable ability for self-consciousness is like a switch that is completely off and then suddenly, as if by magic, turned fully on.
Rather, the consensus and commonsense view is that the ability to experience self-consciousness develops gradually (and can be lost gradually, too, as in the case of dementia). Thus, from the very outset, the revisionist account of personhood was open to the possibility that a human being increases in personal value up to the point he or she becomes a full person. On this basis, bioethical references to “quasi” or “partial” or “potential” persons are very common, and usually indicate a moral worth on the personhood scale somewhere between null and full. The alleged increase in moral worth is not ad hoc: It tracks the human being’s increasing though incomplete appropriation of the ability to do what counts as the criterion for personhood. No longer is there any need to appeal to implausible magic moments or magic points, leaving the plausibility of the revisionist account intact.
Or so it seemed. The reason why the solution appeared to work so well is that up to the point of achieving self-consciousness there was a gradated, proportionate, and isomorphic parallel between the human being’s growth in and toward the relevant criterion and his moral worth. No arbitrary, ad hoc, abrupt change in moral status occurred.REF But if the revisionist account of personhood was to be credible it had to be fully consistent. And that entails a very serious problem. For it is generally accepted by philosophers (and by cognitive scientists) that degrees of self-consciousness are found beyond a minimally substantive point that acts as a plausible anchor for revisionist personhood.REF Indeed, it is likely more accurate to speak of different levels and depths of self-consciousness than of linear degrees, making the idea of an invariant, fixed point of self-consciousness corresponding to the personhood-conferring metric even less plausible.REF
Hence, we are left with this picture by the revisionist account of personhood when informed by the dominant view of self-consciousness: There is a “point” at which a non-intellectually disabled developing human being achieves a level of the capacity for self-consciousness high enough to suffice for counting as a person, and, beyond this, there are human persons with higher levels of this capacity. If the revisionist account of personhood is to maintain internal consistency in light of this picture and is to avoid the arbitrary and ad hoc positing of a magic point at which an increase in moral status no longer tracks (in effect, is proportionate with) an increase in the capacity for self-consciousness, then it follows that it will not only need to accept the existence of quasi or partial persons, but of various degrees of “supra” persons too.
This is precisely the conclusion drawn over the past 10 or so years by respected philosophers like Jeff McMahan,REF Richard Arneson,REF and Christopher Knapp.REF They are not particularly comfortable with the conclusion, since they are proponents of the revisionist account, but they are clearheaded and honest enough to follow their personhood argument where it leads.
It is obvious that the idea of a gradated series of supra persons over and above normal persons destroys outright the idea of fundamental human equality. (The destruction is thoroughgoing, because there will be many supra persons with lesser moral worth than other supra persons on this account.) As the earlier treatment of the UDHR indicated, fundamental equality of human rights and human rights subjects are essential features of the basic meaning of human rights. So the revisionist account of personhood is incompatible with human rights even on the assumption that it can be just to exclude some more marginalized classes of human beings from human rights protection.
Now it might appear open to a proponent of the revisionist account to save it in one of two ways. He or she could simply abandon the idea of gradated personhood altogether, thus saving the account from serious internal inconsistency and from the elitism entailed by it. But that move introduces massive arbitrariness into the position: At every pre-magic level of the relevant capacity being reached, even at the level only ever-so-slightly below the magic level, the human being has no personal worth, while for every increase in the relevant capacity post-magic point it makes absolutely no difference at all to the worth of the human being. The obvious arbitrariness of this approach is recognized by almost all proponents of personhood revisionism, and so few, if any, of them today endorse it.
A more promising savings clause is this: Bite the bullet and insist on thoroughgoing internal consistency, yet deny that the differences in moral status above the “normal” personhood line are significant enough to require practical (as distinct from theoretical) abandonment of fundamental human rights equality. This move, too, however, is unsuccessful. If being situated a little below the personhood-conferring line makes one a partial person, and if it is the case that there is no principled difficulty with killing partial persons compared with killing persons, then it follows that relatively small differences in moral worth on this revisionist account can, in fact, entail drastic differences in what counts as permissible and impermissible treatment.
We now arrive at the deep, human rights–disintegrating flaw of the whole revisionist approach. This is something that even its most clearheaded proponents do not see clearly.REF In proposing that there is any gradation at all within personhood, even only a gradation below a magic line (in effect, only in terms of partial personhood), revisionist proponents commit themselves to viewing personhood as a non-fundamental type of moral worth, one that shares a common metric by which it can be calculated and weighed, and therefore is commensurable with other of its instantiations; non-unique in any of its instantiations; non-fundamental (in effect, not an end in itself); and violable (since an entity participating to some extent in personhood can have his or her core interests intentionally harmed through being killed).
With these concessions made, one is thereby committed to seeing personhood in utilitarian, not natural rights, terms. As per the earlier treatment of the right to life, utilitarian ethics guides action by appeal to a greater good of some sort being produced by one choice over its alternative(s). To make sense of the idea of measuring moral-type goods against one another, there must be a common metric by which to measure them. Natural law ethics rightfully denies there is. The most fundamental morally relevant goods do not share a plausible common metric—what is the common denominator shared by life and friendship and artistic creativity, for example?
Because the most fundamental goods are personal goods, it stands to reason that there is no reductive common metric that can weigh the worth of persons against one another. Each individual person possesses a unique, incommensurable worth; the worth of persons is priceless, and as such their dignity is inviolable. This view of the human dignity proper to persons explains why each of us has a right to life against being intentionally killed, no matter how many other innocent, brilliant, or politically influential persons stand to benefit from the cessation of our existence. Utilitarianism, unwilling to recognize the incommensurable, fundamental, inviolable worth of any moral-type good, even persons themselves, stands unable to justify human rights.REF
So for utilitarianism no one is a person in the true human rights sense; no one possesses inviolable, priceless human dignity. And any position that concedes that personhood has a measure and a price, so that some are more persons than others who are only “quasi” or “partial” persons, and concedes that these others can have their most basic interests deliberately destroyed on the condition that persons overall benefit (“greater good”), is a position that is implicitly utilitarianREF and cannot credibly affirm what is affirmed by Article 3 of the UDHR: “Everyone has a right to life.”
Do not think this is a question of mere ethical theory. One of the factors behind the inclusion of that right in the UDHR was repugnance at the National Socialist euthanasia law targeting, in particular, the intellectually disabledREF—a law justified on utilitarian grounds and with many legal, social, and scholarly precursors within enlightened, progressive Western democracies at that time.REF
The revisionist account of personhood is fatal for the whole of human rights. Divorcing human nature from personhood and positing the attainment of some heightened, immediately exercisable capacity as the criterion for personhood will cash out in one of two ways. If it avoids directly entailing degrees of personhood, it will be utterly arbitrary and thus discrediting of human rights itself, and leave a variety of innocent, vulnerable human beings—born and unborn—without any human rights protection whatsoever. Or, if the divorce is managed in a way whereby it is non-arbitrary and internally consistent, it will end up rejecting the twin truths that all persons are fundamentally equal in moral worth and possess rights that protect them from having their interests deliberately harmed via utilitarian-type calculations. No man is an island, John Donne said, and the bell tolls for us all.
Paths Forward
There is an important role for academic-educational initiatives to explore the deep meaning of human rights. Too few leaders and thinkers are aware of the intellectual threat posed to human rights from within jurisdictions that historically championed them. It is remarkable, for instance, how under-discussed the concessions of McMahan, Arneson, and Knapp are in current debates and literature, given the tightness of their arguments and the stunning and devastating reach of those arguments’ implications. Maybe those who expect to see a monster under the bed tend not to look.
Much more scholarly work needs to be done in this area and in human rights legal and moral theory more generally. This is very much a practical recommendation since the UDHR itself was based on a tradition of thought as much as on a tradition of law and practice.
An urgent and under-appreciated human rights issue is the rogue deliverances of human rights treaty bodies. It is imperative that adherents to authentic human rights formally and openly push back against treaty-monitoring bodies’ undermining of human rights protections. Currently, treaty-monitoring bodies face little, if any, principled state opposition. The effect of this omission is to create the impression in the public, political, and, increasingly, judicial mind that such bodies are fair and even legally authoritative interpreters of human rights law. The falsity of this impression serves to weaken the meaning, standing, and integrity of actual international human rights law as found in human rights treaties.
Further, there is the real possibility that if states continue to remain passive toward or acquiesce in the faulty pronouncements of treaty-monitoring bodies, then those pronouncements could attain the status of customary human rights law and/or such passivity/acquiescence may count as “subsequent practice” for the purposes of interpreting the meaning of human rights treaty law as per Article 31(3)(b) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties. Of note as regards the issue of “subsequent practice” is that the International Law Commission has recently affirmed that treaty bodies’ pronouncements can contribute toward “subsequent practice” if endorsed (or perhaps even non-opposed) by the relevant state.REF So while currently it is very widely accepted, including by the International Law AssociationREF and even revisionist human rights scholars,REF that the conclusions and findings of treaty-monitoring bodies are not legally binding and do not form part of human rights law, this could very well change in the future—and change quite quickly at that.
Recommendations
What can be done? I will briefly outline four possibilities and offer a judgment on each. (No doubt there are more avenues to explore, and others should dedicate time to considering what these might be.)
- Make efforts to alter the consensus philosophical composition of these bodies in a way that makes them more faithful to the human rights philosophy. States do have power to elect the members of these bodies. To the best of my knowledge, there has hitherto been little coordinated effort among states to promote the election of authentic defenders of human rights to various treaty-monitoring bodies—so there is much room for improvement in this regard. Realistically, though, in the short term, it will be a difficult task to coordinate the election of a sufficient number of authentic human rights defenders to a particular body so as to shift that body’s majority view on important matters like the right to life. More immediately realizable, and probably more efficient, options are available.
- Engage with treaty-monitoring bodies when they are in the process of formulating a new General Comment. This approach is one already taken by adherents to authentic human rights. This happened recently during drafting by the HRC of its General Comment 36 (on the right to life). Pro-life academics, nongovernmental organizations (NGOs), and states made submissions urging the HRC to reject the idea that the right to life somehow entails a right to abortion.REF Their efforts were well-intentioned but ultimately doomed to failure.
- The current consensus philosophical position of the HRC, which is antithetical to authentic human rights, meant that deliberations over General Comment 36 were virtually certain to end up rejecting the right to life of unborn children and endorsing a right to abortion.REF Unless approach (1) is successfully pursued—at least in part—approach (2) will be unrealizable.
- Use pro-life-inclined governments’ formal responses to U.N. treaty-monitoring bodies’ “periodic reviews” to advance criticisms of said bodies’ questions (which are often ideologically loaded against the meaning of the relevant treaty itself) and “jurisprudence.” This is a more immediately realizable approach, does not involve a huge amount of coordination, and will have a positive impact.
- Current practice is generally for states to acquiesce in the supposed integrity of the review process by neither challenging the basis of the questions put to them nor pre-emptively responding to the likely “findings” of the body against them. At most, states that avoid amending domestic law in line with a U.N. body’s expectations will cite their dualist legal system or some other intricacy of their domestic law. But often the questions and deliverances of the treaty-monitoring body will presuppose the existence of a “right” not part (either explicitly or implicitly) of the treaty of which the body is a function.
- States, therefore, can and should use their official responses to formally criticize and reject faulty interpretations of human rights treaties by U.N. bodies and highlight instances where such bodies are acting ultra vires by attempting to unilaterally amend binding international human rights law (the content of which is formed by textual provisions read in light of supplementary means of treaty interpretation, as per the VCLT). State parties can do this in both the “State Parties Reports,” the initial step of the review process, and then in their response to the U.N. bodies’ “Lists of Issues” (a response titled “Replies to LOIs”).REF
- U.N. bodies’ “Concluding Observations,” the final step of the review process, would thereby be forced to take notice of criticisms directed towards the U.N. body’s assertions—and to formally engage with those criticisms in a way they do not currently have to when NGOs criticize U.N. interpretations of human rights during the oral presentation part of the periodic review process.
- Potentially, this could: (1) force U.N. bodies (or at least certain of its members) to critically reflect on their own operations, competence, and fidelity to human rights law; (2) encourage other states to question the deliverances of U.N. bodies on human rights grounds; (3) dampen judicial enthusiasm for citing the work of treaty-monitoring bodies; (4) lessen the aura of uncontroversial authoritativeness of treaty-monitoring bodies in the public and official mind; and (5) motivate and provide official data for scholarly reflection on the trajectory of human rights law, theory, and practice.
- More importantly, though, this measure would place a substantial (and possibly insurmountable) obstacle in the path of treaty bodies’ pronouncements forming either customary human rights law or contributing towards “subsequent practice” as per Article 31(3)(b) of the VCLT.
- The effectiveness of the implementation of this recommendation would be greatly enhanced if formal state objections to a treaty body’s interpretation of human rights law were legally well grounded, in effect, if the objections cohered with the legal hermeneutics endorsed by Articles 31 and 32 of the VCLT (see discussion, infra). Usually only a small number of civil servants/department officials have direct responsibility for the drafting of official responses to U.N. bodies, so it should not be difficult to coordinate the practical implementation of this recommendation.
- In line with and supplementing the previous recommendation, states should also submit interpretative declarations to the human rights treaties they have ratified (or even just signed) outlining that they interpret these treaties in accordance with Articles 31 and 32 of the VCLT. Normally interpretative declarations (which are distinct from reservations) are communicated by states upon signing, ratifying, or acceding to a treaty, but international law does not stipulate that their communication is restricted to those official acts. In fact, the International Law Commission accepts the legitimacy of the “late formulation” of interpretative declarations,REF as does the U.N.REF and the Council of Europe.REF
- The VCLT itself is uncontroversially authoritative in international law. It has been ratified by 114 states and is regarded as a codification of existing customary law. So it is difficult to imagine how an international actor could object to an interpretative declaration that affirms a particular state interprets a treaty it is party to in accordance with the VCLT.
- The VCLT’s attractiveness is in its reasonableness. Article 31(1) states that a treaty “shall be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose.” Article 32 deals with supplementary means of interpretation in cases in which the meaning of a treaty provision is ambiguous. In particular, it mentions having recourse to the travaux as a supplementary means of treaty interpretation.
- Of course, a good faith reading of the express terms of a human rights treaty in light of its object and purpose and supplemented by an awareness of its travaux cannot sustain the claim that there is an international human right to abortion. Hence it is no surprise that treaty-monitoring bodies that affirm such a right adopt nothing like a VCLT interpretative methodology (or any principled hermeneutic methodology at all—they simply trade in sheer assertion).
- Entering an interpretative declaration indicating commitment to the VCLT would affirm the actual meaning of the treaty as well as legally and politically disarm the influence of treaty-monitoring bodies when they interpret that treaty in a free-wheeling manner expressive of their own philosophical convictions. All the effects outlined above in relation to point three apply here, too. The more states that can be encouraged to implement points three and four, the more treaty-monitoring bodies will lose political credibility—and the less they will develop customary legal authority or indirect positive legal authority from being considered as contributing towards “subsequent practice.”
Conclusion
Here, I suggest two possible basic outlines for what the relevant interpretative declaration may look like, one more general and the other more targeted:
- “The government of x declares that only interpretations of the present treaty which accord with Articles 31 and 32 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, which x has ratified, shall be considered by x for the purpose of amending domestic law.”
- As above with (1) with the addition of the following: “The government of x does not accept the authority of a third-party body to unilaterally alter treaty provisions agreed to by x upon ratification of the present treaty, either by deletion, addition, or amendment of treaty provisions. The present treaty makes no provision for such an authority.”
What is needed is for one or a number of states to take the first step and to formally and substantially push back against the abuse of prestige by rogue treaty-monitoring bodies, an abuse that it greatly damaging the credibility and practical effect of genuine human rights. Doing so is practical; not doing so will make adherence to genuine human rights increasingly impractical.REF
Thomas Finegan, PhD, is a lecturer in theology and religious studies at Mary Immaculate College, Ireland; Vice-Chair of the Board of Governors of the Anscombe Bioethics Centre, Oxford; a member of the Working Group (religious education) of the Council for Catechetics of the Irish Catholic Bishops’ Conference; and a member of the Bioethics Consultative Group of the Irish Catholic Bishops’ Conference.