The Civil Rights Act of 1964 as a Teacher of Virtue

Legal Memo The Constitution

The Civil Rights Act of 1964 as a Teacher of Virtue

June 11, 2024 About an hour read Download Report
canaparo
Senior Legal Fellow, Edwin Meese III Center
GianCarlo is a Senior Legal Fellow in The Heritage Foundation’s Edwin Meese III Center for Legal and Judicial Studies.

Summary

Conservative critics argue that the Civil Rights Act of 1964 is responsible for the many cultural, political, and legal ills that plague America today and that the act is either the cause or at least a major cause of a largely successful campaign to replace the Constitution with a new civil rights regime. Putting aside the complicated question of tracing the causal factors (philosophical, cultural, political, legal, etc.) of each identified ill and weighing their causal effects, the argument advanced by conservative critics cannot be complete until they have considered whether the Civil Rights Act has been a good teacher of virtue. The evidence indicates that it has been a good teacher, at least with respect to race.

Key Takeaways

Some conservatives argue that the Civil Rights Act of 1964 laid the foundation for a campaign to replace the Constitution with a new civil rights regime.

These critics argue either that the act’s promise of finally realizing color-blind governance was false or that its corruption was inevitable.

Their argument is at best incomplete because they have overlooked the role that the Civil Rights Act has played as a teacher of virtue.

Is the Civil Rights Act of 1964 a good law or a bad one? There are people of all political stripes on both sides of that debate. Many of the act’s supporters consider it to be “the final triumph of the color-blindness principle.”REF Some of its critics agree and dislike the act for that very reason. Collectivists on the political Left, such as critical race theorists and Antiracists, object to the Civil Rights Act because its general and equal protection of individuals’ rights forbids “benign” or “reparative” racial discrimination.REF

On the other side of the political divide, some conservatives criticize the act because, in their view, it handed power to those collectivists, who now use it to discriminate among groups based on ascriptive qualities.REF These conservative critics argue that the act created or, at a minimum, laid the foundation for a new constitution that replaced the old one. This new constitution, they argue, concentrates power in the hands of an out-of-touch elite, severely restricts the freedoms of speech and association, destroys the national identity that is necessary to unite a diverse people, and inflames tribalism and race hatred.REF In short, they argue either that the act’s promise of finally realizing color-blind governance was false or that its corruption was inevitable.

In this paper, I engage this latter group of critics. I claim that their argument is at best incomplete because they have overlooked the role that the Civil Rights Act has played as a teacher of virtue.

I do not engage with the act’s collectivist critics for two reasons: They are likely to reject out of hand the virtue–ethics framework that I employ here,REF and with respect to arguments to which they are likely to listen, there is little to say that has not been said before. Their argument that discrimination is a necessary and efficacious evil has already taken considerable criticism along the lines that “benign” or “reparative” race discrimination tends to produce abundant harms but few if any goods.REF Their argument that discrimination can be a positive good has likewise taken considerable criticism,REF and insofar as their arguments are reformulations of old collectivist arguments, old responses to those arguments still apply.REF There is little if any new ground to attack.REF

The act’s critics on the modern Right, however, having arrived on the field later, enjoy a more peaceful sector. It is not my intention here to commence shelling them. Rather, my intention here is only to shine a spotlight on one important gap in their position. Building on the work of Cathleen Kaveny, who brings “Aquinas’s legal theory into critical conversation with the work of Joseph Raz,” I argue that, at least as to race, the Civil Rights Act of 1964 has been an effective teacher of virtue and that any final judgment about whether the act is good or bad must take its educative effect into consideration.REF It might yet be that the act’s educative effect does not outweigh other considerations. Or it might be that my analysis of its educative effect is erroneous or incomplete. Nevertheless, conservatives who recognize that laws have more than mere material implications must grapple with the question of how the act shapes souls.

Before I begin, I must make two points. First, I engage with the act only on the issue of race (broadly defined to include color, ethnicity, and national origin). The act also includes religion, and Title VII includes sex. Both religion and sex raise issues different from race: religion because in limited circumstances, such as employment in a particular church,REF religious belief or practice may be a legitimate reason to discriminate, and sex because there are differences between all males and all females, but that is not the case with respect to any two people placed in any two of the government-created race categories upon which civil-rights enforcement focuses.REF Rather, because the categories that the government uses are arbitrary, there are infinite types and degrees of diversity among the individuals who may be placed into any of them. I acknowledge that a conclusion that the act has been a good teacher as to race does not end the inquiry into whether it is on the whole a good teacher, but because racial discrimination was the act’s primary target (and to keep this paper to a reasonable length), I limit myself only to the question of race.

Second, although I do not challenge here the argument that the Civil Rights Act is the primary cause of the many ills that its conservative critics identify, I do not concede the argument. I am, in fact, skeptical that conservative critics of the act have isolated the causal effect of the act itself from the causal effect of the myriad other philosophical, cultural, political, and legal developments that came before and after it.REF But that is an argument for another time. Here, I focus only on something that I think conservative critics of the act have neglected: that the act, at least as to race, is likely an effective teacher of virtue.

The Law as a Teacher of Virtue

Law may be downstream of culture, but culture is sometimes downstream of law.REF This is so because, as Cathleen Kaveny puts it, “[a]lways and everywhere, law teaches a moral lesson—it imbues a vision of how the members of a particular society should live their lives together.”REF The law may teach people what is good simply, or it may teach them what is good in relation to the regime alone, but no matter what the law aims to teach, the people it teaches are shaped by its effort.REF Sometimes, the law aims to teach a good lesson and teaches it effectively. Sometimes, the law aims to teach an evil lesson (think laws in Nazi Germany) and teaches it effectively.REF And sometimes the law teaches ineffectively and either accomplishes something other than what it intends or sparks backlash against itself and its intended lesson.REF

America’s checkered history with respect to race means that laws on that topic can be profoundly influential teachers. Of course, the law is not the only teacher. Religious beliefs, political theories, influential leaders, public crises, government policies, and myriad other factors inform the American culture on race and in many cases are themselves shaped by that culture. Every law that touches on race plays a part in this swirling river of rapids, eddies, and backflows. It may be difficult to isolate the contribution of any one law, but whenever one of those laws finds itself under the harsh lights of new and renewed criticism, it is good to make the attempt. The insights that this yields may allow the people to improve the law and therefore themselves. Even if it does not, the attempt is necessary to minimize the risk of wrongly tearing down one of Chesterton’s metaphorical fences.REF

To undertake this attempt, we need a framework for evaluating whether a law has taught well. That framework must do three things: It must identify what law ought to teach, must prescribe how law ought to teach, and must provide a way to measure whether the law has taught well. Building such a framework is a difficult undertaking in any regime, but it is particularly difficult in a pluralistic and liberal republic characterized by nearly limitless choice among conceptions of rightness and among actions. Kaveny has provided a useful framework that I borrow here with some emendations.REF

On the question of what law ought to teach, Kaveny starts from the Thomistic principle “that the major purpose of the law is to lead human beings to virtue.”REF For law to do that well, two things must be true. First, the message that the law teaches must be objectively good.REF A law that teaches evil (again, for example, Nazi laws about Jews) cannot teach well because it cannot lead people to virtue. But moral content is not enough; the law must also inculcate its moral message effectively.REF A law that intends to teach a good lesson but is ignored by the people will not teach well. Thus, Kaveny’s core observation is that a law’s pedagogical function is determined both by the law’s moral content and by its practical ability to impart that content.

There are many virtues that law ought to teach, but different laws are suited to teaching different virtues. Tax law, for example, might be good at teaching the virtue of charity by rewarding it, and administrative law might teach government officials the virtue of practical reason by encouraging them to practice it. Kaveny seems to assume that her framework applies to all sorts of laws, but her framework seems to me best (and perhaps exclusively) suited to coercive laws—laws that prohibit or require certain actions and enforce those demands with penalties. This is so because Kaveny’s primary concern is backlash against laws and the rule of law generally if laws are flouted.REF But if someone refuses to use a tax deduction for charitable giving, there will be no backlash either against the law or against the rule of law. The deduction simply goes unused. The risk of backlash is present only when the law forbids or mandates certain actions. At any rate, because I am concerned here with the Civil Rights Act of 1964, a coercive law that forbids racial discrimination in zones of federal power, Kaveny’s framework is useful even if it does not reach quite as far as she seems to say it does.

Coercive laws aim to teach people virtue by showing them how they should and should not live together.REF Thus, the two virtues that coercive laws must especially teach are prudence and justice.REF Prudence is “the habit of practical reason; it is the virtue that applies right reason to action.”REF Prudence will counsel different actions in different societies because different societies provide different choices to different peoples. A modern, pluralistic, liberal society like ours, for example, provides a greater range of choices than any other.REF The people of that society also view choice itself as essential to human flourishing.REF We need, therefore, a “specification” of prudence suited to our society.REF That specification, Kaveny argues, is “autonomy as conceived by [Joseph] Raz.”REF For Raz, autonomy is not negative freedom—that is, the freedom to act in any way one may wish to act.REF Rather, autonomy is “positive freedom”—the freedom to shape one’s own life toward what is morally good.REF Autonomy requires three things: the mental, emotional, and physical capacity to make choices; the freedom to do so without coercion or manipulation; and an array of morally valuable options from which to choose.REF It does not require the freedom to choose among evil and morally empty options.REF

Prudence is a habit, and autonomy is a type of freedom, so it is not obvious how the latter can be a “partial instantiation” of the former.REF Kaveny argues that the conditions necessary for autonomy are those things that prudence requires for humans to flourish in our social and political context.REF In other words, she seems to argue that in our society, the law should teach prudence by providing and protecting the three requirements of autonomy. It therefore follows that to promote autonomy, the law should support the development of the capacity for choice and prevent others from interfering with that capacity. But it also follows that the law itself may need to be coercive because it must restrict certain evil or empty options.REF

This raises a question that Kaveny does not clearly answer: What source of morality ought to draw the line between good and bad options? As a Catholic, Kaveny might point to the Church’s moral traditions. For my limited purposes here, I need only one moral rule: that it is wrong to discriminate against another person or a group of persons based on their race. I can ground this principle in the classical tradition, the Christian tradition, or the American tradition.REF The point is that if it is immoral to choose to discriminate based on race, then the law might foster autonomy if it eliminated that choice.REF

Autonomy has a social dimension: People cannot be autonomous in isolation.REF If people are to shape their lives toward what is morally good, others must provide and protect autonomy’s three requirements,REF none of which can exist without “a firm and steady social commitment.”REF For example, someone must teach a child what is true and right if the child is to form the capacity to choose. Likewise, someone must protect that child from coercion by bad actors. Finally, someone must protect the availability of good options and limit evil ones. Other people, then, have a duty to form and educate individuals, to protect them from coercion and manipulation, and to make available good choices while limiting the availability of bad or empty ones.REF In other words, every individual owes these duties to the people he encounters and to his society in general.REF This duty is fulfilled through the second virtue that law must teach: justice.

Aquinas’s conception of justice, which Kaveny incorporates into her framework, includes general justice, which “directs man immediately to the common good,” and particular justice, which “direct[s] a man immediately to the good of another individual.”REF As with prudence, justice needs a specification suited to our society.REF Our society is enormous and impersonal.REF The common good seems like a distant abstraction and our ability to contribute to it like a raindrop in the sea. Most of the people that we live with are unseen or anonymous, and the effects of most of our choices on them are unknown or unconsidered. It is therefore very easy for individuals simply to detach their thoughts from the common good and from the particular justice that they owe to the people with whom they interact.

Given all this, Kaveny argues that the specification of justice that is suited to our society is “solidarity” as defined by Pope John Paul II.REF Solidarity is “a firm and persevering determination to commit oneself to the common good; that is to say to the good of all and of each individual, because we are all really responsible for all.”REF Kaveny argues that solidarity “provide[s] necessary shape” to justice in three ways.REF It focuses individuals’ attention on the needs of their many fellow citizens who live out of sight;REF encourages individuals to “transcend consideration of the justice of [their] actions in isolation” and to think of their larger effects across society;REF and attunes individuals to society’s duty to protect the three requirements of autonomy: capacity for choice, freedom from coercion, and morally good options.REF

Solidarity seems to serve a modest role in Kaveny’s framework because it provides no clear instruction with respect to how people ought to treat others in particular circumstances and, with respect to any particular choice, adds no guidance beyond that already provided by the maxim “give[] to every man his due.”REF Rather, solidarity seems only to say that as people in huge and anonymous societies go about their daily lives, they should be mindful of the effects of their choices on other people and on the common good. In that case, to say that the law should teach solidarity is to say that the law ought to foster a sense of national unity or civic friendship. It ought to remind people that they are not islands in a sea of faceless bodies, or even members of culturally isolated tribes, but friends, citizens, and countrymen—equals.

The next question that Kaveny’s framework answers is: How should law teach and, just as important, not teach? As with the question of what law ought to teach, Kaveny starts with Aquinas and his recognition that there are “practical and moral limitations on the power of positive law.”REF Again, her core claim is that law can fail to teach well in two ways: either by teaching an evil lesson or by failing to teach a good lesson. She cites Aquinas, who in turn relies on Isidore of Seville, who said that “[l]aw shall be virtuous, just, possible to nature, according to the custom of the country, suitable to place and time, necessary, useful; clearly expressed, lest by its obscurity it lead to misunderstanding; framed for no private benefit but for the common good.”REF From this, Kaveny derives a list of limitations on coercive laws’ ability to teach. First, coercive laws must not ask men to be angels. Those laws teach their lessons to ordinary people under threat of punishment, so they must offer “only the most elementary lessons in the ways of virtue.”REF Second, coercive laws must not deviate too far from the culture of the people they govern; if they do, they will be ineffective because the people will ignore, rebel against, or refuse to enforce them. Finally, coercive laws must be concrete and intelligible so that they clearly guide the people toward the common good.REF If coercive laws ignore these constraints, they are likely to fail to teach anything, and it will not matter that the lesson they aim to teach is good.

The practical concern that Kaveny identifies is the backlash that can erupt when the law is flouted. Thus, again, Kaveny’s framework seems suited particularly, if not exclusively, to coercive laws. Coercion can be an effective teaching tool, but its use carries risks. Consider Kaveny’s example of a criminal law against wantonly killing small bugs in the wild.REF It is immoral to kill any creature wantonly, but a law against killing small bugs wantonly would violate Isidore’s practical limitations. For one thing, detecting that crime would involve government agents following people out into the wilderness—intrusive surveillance out of proportion to the act. For another, that surveillance would hinder other goods such as peacefully enjoying nature and the private association that makes community possible.REF Likewise, prosecuting that crime would consume scarce resources that could be used to prosecute more serious crimes, and the manifest unreasonableness in the eyes of most people of punishing others for killing a bug might cause people to flout the law.REF

If a law is flouted, there is a risk that the people will disdain not only that law, but the rule of law generally. Even more concerning is the risk that if the law deviates greatly from the people’s customs, they will come to disdain the entire legal regime.REF Prudence therefore counsels lawmakers to shift custom gently rather than crash the law into it, for if the law crashes into custom and fails to shift it, the law, the rule of law, and the entire system of laws could be dashed to bits.REF Consider Kaveny’s example of a small, isolated, and lawless mining town in the Wild West.REF A citizens’ brigade wants to end the town’s many vices, including robbery, murder, and dueling, but the brigade is vastly outnumbered by brigands. The brigade would accomplish nothing by outlawing those vices. The law would be revealed as impotent—a thing for the brigands to mock and flout simply because they can.REF In that situation, Kaveny argues that the brigade should change the law slowly without reforming “too much too fast.”REF In general, Kaveny calls for a “gradualist approach toward eliminating even serious moral wrongs.”REF

On this point, Kaveny has attracted criticism that is relevant to my use of her framework. Kevin Flannery interprets Kaveny as saying that where a society holds strongly to an evil custom, law should not try to change that custom.REF I doubt, however, that this is the best way to read Kaveny. In my view, Kaveny does not argue that laws should not try to change evil customs, but that there are times when coercive laws alone cannot change evil customs and that, in those circumstances, other means are necessary. Again, her example of the lawless Wild West town is instructive. There, the law wields no force sufficient to prevent the brigands from ignoring it,REF so Kaveny urges the citizens’ brigade to make great efforts to change the culture first so that it is primed to accept a change in the law.REF But even then, she does not rule out use of the law as part of those efforts. For example, if the goal is to outlaw dueling, she suggests that the law should first set down a dueling code that forbids duels that do not conform to it.REF That code might, for example, mandate “cooling off periods” or require a dueler who kills his opponent to take some measure of financial responsibility for his opponent’s family.REF People might obey a dueling code even if they would disobey a dueling prohibition, and although the code would not eradicate dueling, it might bolster a larger campaign aimed at teaching people that dueling is wrong. This seems to me the best reading of Kaveny’s argument.

Kaveny does, however, seem to miss something important: The law’s ability to change an evil custom depends partially on how strongly the custom is held, who holds it, and how much force the law can bring to bear against it or them. For example, if dueling is a weakly held custom, then there is little reason to fear backlash against a law forbidding it. Likewise, if the evil custom is strongly held by only a small but powerful minority of people, a lawmaker need worry less about backlash if the law can eliminate that minority’s power. In fact, in that circumstance, it may be good for the law to move quickly and forcefully to depose that minority. The point is that the prudential concerns about whether the law is appropriate to the nature and customs of the people cannot be distilled so easily into a general rule of gradualist reform. Sometimes, the law can and should move quickly.

In summary, Kaveny argues that laws in a pluralistic liberal society ought to teach autonomy and solidarity, and she argues that certain practical limitations constrain the means of teaching. From these conclusions she derives several characteristics common to coercive laws that teach well, to which I add one of my own:

  1. They show citizens a positive vision of how they should live their lives together that “exemplifies the fruitful relationship between autonomy and solidarity;”
  2. They signal lawmakers’ hope that citizens will not merely comply with the law, but will embrace the law’s positive vision in their lives and relationships;
  3. They do not punish citizens for failing to exhibit all virtues, but rather limit themselves to punishing vicious external actions; and (my own)
  4. They move with speed and force prudentially tailored to the nature and customs of the people.REF

Kaveny asserts without discussion that the Civil Rights Act of 1964 fulfills her requirements. I agree that it fulfills hers, as well as mine, and explain why in the following section.

The Civil Rights Act as a Good Teacher

To understand whether the Civil Rights Act of 1964 fulfills these four requirements, it is first necessary to understand where it came from and what it does. The act’s context and provenance will reveal the customs and nature of the people it governs.REF Its content will reveal whether its lesson is good and whether its means of teaching are appropriately constrained.REF

In a direct sense, the act’s context and provenance were the customs and laws of Jim Crow and the civil rights movement that sought to end them. But in a proximate—yet more meaningful sense—the act’s roots stretch back to the principle that “all men are created equal [and] endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights.”REF That principle, enshrined in the nation’s creedal document, established a key national custom—a custom often more aspirational than real, but one that served as the linchpin of the perpetual debate about what national virtue looks like. Those who wanted civic equality to transcend race built their arguments on that principle. Frederick Douglass, for example, called it “the ringbolt to the chain of your nation’s destiny” and a “saving principle.”REF Abraham Lincoln called it the animating principle of the Republic and the “immortal emblem of humanity.”REF Meanwhile, those who wanted race to determine civic standing had to wrestle with the same principle. Some, like Stephen Douglas, denied that black people were “men,” and others, like Alexander Stephens, dismissed the principle as “an error.”REF But everyone on every side of the ancient yet ever-living debate about natural and civic equality has had to engage with the principle.

The principle animated early opposition to slavery, the Union cause in the Civil War, Reconstruction, the Reconstruction amendments, and the diverse civil rights laws passed during the hundred years between the end of the Civil War and the 1964 act.REF Yet throughout that time, the American people were only ever riven over racial equality. To be sure, the debate was never static. At times, those who embraced racial equality seemed to have won resounding victories just moments before suffering devastating defeats. Reconstruction, for example, likely seemed to some to be a great victory. Consider Homer Adolph Plessy, the man who would give his name to the infamous case and famous dissent.REF Born in New Orleans in the late 1850s or early 1860s, he lived in a Louisiana when he was young that was very different from the Louisiana of his old age. Early in his life, schools were integrated, interracial marriage was legal, and black men voted and held high state offices including the governorship.REF All of this was enforced by Union soldiers and the custom rekindled by abolition’s triumph.REF Neither would last. Both retreated, and Jim Crow swept over the South and smothered what must have felt to some like the final victory of the equality principle.REF Yet for nearly a century, in the South, the custom of Jim Crow would win out over the custom of the Declaration.

About one hundred years after Plessy’s birth, Congress passed the Civil Rights Act of 1964.REF President John F. Kennedy had sent the bill to Congress the year before “not merely for reasons of economic efficiency, world diplomacy and domestic tranquility—but, above all, because it is right.”REF The bill followed a long civil rights campaign that marched explicitly under the banner of the “immortal emblem of humanity”REF—the “magnificent words” that “all men are created equal.”REF

To give legal effect to a principle that, despite all of the other laws on the books that were meant to uphold it, was derelict in much of the country, the act:REF

  • Declared that its purposes were to “enforce the constitutional right to vote,” “protect constitutional rights in public facilities and public education,” “prevent discrimination in federally assisted programs,” and give the executive and judicial branches the power to enforce it;REF
  • Prohibited state election officials from applying different standards and procedures to different voters and from using literacy tests to exclude voters;REF
  • Prohibited intentional race discrimination in public accommodations and facilities (exempting private clubs), education, federally assisted programs, and employment (with the caveat that the act could not be interpreted to require preferential treatment);REF
  • Established civil penalties for violations and, in cases of contempt, misdemeanor criminal penalties;REF
  • Created or empowered institutions to investigate and enforce these provisions;REF and
  • Created a Community Relations Service and other “training institutes” without investigative or enforcement power whose mission it is to teach the act’s underlying aims through training and dispute mediation.REF

A Positive Vision of Autonomy and Solidarity. The Civil Rights Act provided Americans with a positive vision of how they ought to live together. Although everyone knew that its primary target was discrimination that targeted black Americans, the act was universal in all of its terms. It declared its intent to protect the constitutional rights of all Americans, not only the rights of a specific group. It declared its intent to prohibit all racial discrimination within its reach, not only discrimination against specific races.REF And it applied to “any individual,” “all persons,” and “citizens.”REF

No poll worker could discriminate against black voters under the act’s terms, but neither could poll workers discriminate against white voters. No official could exclude black Americans from public parks, but neither could officials exclude Mexican Americans from those spaces.REF No federally funded program could deny its resources to black Americans, but neither could it deny them to Japanese Americans. No employer could fire someone because of his skin color, but neither could an employer be forced to hire someone because of his skin color.REF No school board could keep black and white children in separate schools, but neither could it assign students to schools “in order to overcome racial imbalance.”REF The tool of discrimination was forbidden no matter the intent behind it.REF

True, everyone knew that the act mainly targeted discrimination against black Americans, but by employing universal language, it targeted not only that particular evil, but also the general evil underneath it: the idea that it is right to discriminate against any person because of his race. In this way, the act gestured to a high moral principle with roots in both the Judeo–Christian and American traditions. Supporters of that principle could claim to march under the banners of Imago Dei and Saint Paul’s declaration that “ye are all one in Christ Jesus.”REF They could count on their side the best vision of the Founders—“statesmen, patriots and heroes” who “contended for no class, nor condition [but] for humanity.”REF And they could find in their arsenal all the moral authority of those who had fought and died for the ideal that “[o]ur constitution is color-blind, and neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens.”REF So armed, they fought for black people not because they were black but because they were people.

That vision fostered autonomy and solidarity. In accordance with its vision, the act restricted an evil choice while preserving a range of good choices. It also opened a range of good choices that Jim Crow had closed through coercion. Not only did Jim Crow encourage (and in some contexts require) Americans to separate themselves according to immoral customs and rules, but so too did it discourage (and in some contexts forbid) Americans from interacting with each other in fruitful ways. For example, Jim Crow’s customs and laws forbade black and white children from playing and learning together and thus restricted a fruitful freedom of association.REF Similarly, Jim Crow forbade white and black Christians from worshipping together and thus restricted a fruitful freedom of religious association and exercise. So too did Jim Crow’s customs punish speech that challenged it, thus restricting fruitful uses of that freedom.REF Finally, the act told each American that he was united with his neighbor, no matter his color, through shared humanity, citizenship, and legal equality. Everyone had the same rights and was entitled to the same protections.

Hope for a Broader Embrace of that Vision. The act did more than just convey that positive vision. It also expressed lawmakers’ hope that the vision would be more broadly embraced. Its universal language and rejection of a general evil reminded Americans of the higher principle that it aimed to teach. The act recognized that there is no legitimate difference between people of one color and another that justifies differential treatment in any zone within the law’s reach. Thus, it suggested that if there was no just reason to exclude people from all of those zones because of their color, there also must be no just reason to exclude people from purely private zones on that basis. It suggested, too, that if there was no just reason to exclude people even from private zones because of their color, there could be no just reason privately to hate them on that basis. Thus, it encouraged Americans to see people as fellow citizens before seeing them as members of a racial group.REF

Moreover, despite Supreme Court decisions taking an expansive view of the Commerce Clause, which extended the act’s reach, the act was still limited in scope.REF Even so, it reached as broadly as it could so that even spheres beyond its reach were never very far from spheres where its moral vision shone, and where it could not extend its reach directly, it invited people to approach it by establishing the Community Relations Service and training programs, which have no power but exist to help people deal with “difficulties relating to discriminatory practices” and to foster “peaceful relations among the citizens of the community.”REF The act requires no one to use these services, but it hopes that people will choose to do so. The Community Relations Service, for example, provides its services to any “interested person.”REF The act likewise attempts to remove practical hurdles that might prevent someone from using these services. For example, it encourages the Commissioner of Education to pay stipends and travel expenses to any educators who choose to attend the training institutes.REF In all of these ways, it hopes to inspire a broader embrace of its moral vision.

Punishment Limited to Vicious External Action. Nevertheless, the act did not attempt to outlaw private thoughts or actions beyond the reach of Congress’s Commerce Clause powers. It prohibits only certain discriminatory external actions. People can hate privately if they choose to do so. They can say horrible things if they choose to do so. They are free even to discriminate in their private clubs and social groups if they choose to do so. This restraint is important in coercive laws not only because it reduces the risk of backlash, but also because it does not endanger the goods that can be found in private thought, association, and speech.REF As Kaveny explains with an analogy to the Supreme Court’s free speech doctrine, “[w]e refuse to prohibit all sorts of malicious and useless speech because we are afraid that such measures will also impede the sort of vigorous political discussion so necessary in a representative democracy.”REF The Civil Rights Act follows the same thinking, prohibiting only certain plainly immoral actions that harm others.

On this point, the act’s conservative critics might disagree vigorously. Even if they concede Gail Heriot’s argument that the restrictions on free speech and free association that they lament are largely caused by amendments and judicial decisions, they might still argue that the act, unamended, is at least a partial cause.REF Christopher Caldwell, for example, quoting Herbert Wechsler, argues that “integration forces an association upon those for whom it is unpleasant or repugnant.”REF Quoting Leo Strauss, Caldwell argues that “[t]he prohibition against every ‘discrimination’ would mean the abolition of the private sphere, the denial of the difference between the state and society, in a word, the destruction of liberal society.”REF

I concede the truth of both statements but deny that the Civil Rights Act of 1964 either mandates integration or prohibits every discrimination. As to forced integration, the act prohibits it with respect to both education and employment.REF To be sure, the Supreme Court has required integration and race-based employment decisions, and the 1991 amendment to the act, which codified the Court’s disparate impact theory, also does so.REF But the 1964 Act, by its own terms, does not.

As to discrimination, the act does not prohibit every discrimination; it chiefly prohibits only one particular and morally repugnant sort and only in certain spheres. It hopes for the abolition of race discrimination everywhere, but it does not require it. If some of the act’s critics argue that no meaningful line can be drawn between prohibiting some discrimination in some places and prohibiting all discrimination everywhere, then I respond that this is true only if we lack the means to distinguish between moral and immoral discrimination.REF But we do not.

It is not impossible to draw lines between permissible and impermissible sorts of discrimination: We do so constantly. No reasonable person, for example, would say that it is unjust to discriminate against a small person when hiring a linebacker, just as no reasonable person would say that it is unjust to discriminate against a large person when hiring a jockey. Nor would any reasonable person say that it is unjust for the Civil Rights Act to allow churches to discriminate based on religious belief when hiring ministers.REF But no reasonable person would say that is right to discriminate against small people, large people, or religious people when hiring a software engineer. What we do naturally in these cases is match discriminatory actions with the contexts in which they are just. Simply put, we require that ends be just and that the means match them. We do this constantly, and so does the judicial system.

This “means–end fit” analysis is the essential stuff of equal protection doctrine.REF The doctrine’s fundamental purpose is to give life to the maxim that “like things should be treated alike, and differently things differently” by making sure that disparate treatment is done with proper means aimed at proper ends.REF We need not explore further here how that analysis works; we need only observe that the doctrine governing these questions is incredibly sophisticated, even if imperfect.REF Put simply, a ban on racial discrimination in certain spheres by no means implies a ban on all forms of discrimination in all spheres.

Speed and Force Prudentially Tailored. Finally, the speed and force that the Civil Rights Act used to teach its moral lessons were prudentially tailored to the nature of the people and to their customs. Recall that the Civil Rights Act of 1964 was not the first attempt to teach the American people this moral lesson. Far from it: It followed a long list of other laws that tried and failed to teach what the 1964 act later taught. The Reconstruction Amendments failed as soon as Union troops and the post-war moral fervor retreated (to say nothing of the judiciary’s role in undermining the amendments).REF The Civil Rights Act of 1866 failed.REF The Enforcement Acts failed.REF The Civil Rights Act of 1875 failed.REF So too did the Civil Rights Acts of 1957 and 1960.REF

Three things had changed. First, the custom of Jim Crow was at its weakest, and the custom of the Declaration was the strongest it had been since the end of the Civil War. Second, the custom of Jim Crow was strongly held by a small but powerful minority. Third, the act arrayed sufficient force against that minority to prevent much of the anticipated backlash.

Support for these claims comes readily to hand from C. Vann Woodward’s remarkable observation that what followed the 1964 act’s passage was not the “wave of defiance” that some predicted, but rather “a wave of peaceful compliance” everywhere but in certain rural parts of the South.REF No doubt this was likely due to the cultural foundation laid under the law by the civil rights movement and other positive developments in race relations like President Harry Truman’s decision to integrate military units.REF Its appeal to Christianity and to the nation’s founding creed and its stoic suffering in the face of violence whittled down “[a]ll but the most incorrigible white resistance.”REF By 1960, both political parties had made opposition to segregation and support for sit-in demonstrations parts of their platforms,REF and with passage of the act, the federal government, for the first time since Reconstruction, had the power (along with the political will provided by the changing culture) to enforce its moral vision against public and private actors who enforced an immoral vision. The act was well tailored to these circumstances, capitalizing on the return to the custom of the Declaration while arming people who embraced that custom with the powers necessary to depose the powerful minority that rejected it.

Given the changing culture, critics might argue that the Act was not necessary: that circumstances would have improved without it. Insofar as their claim is that the conditions of daily life for black Americans would have improved eventually on their own, that is a question of alternative history, and because I am not a historian, the only answer I can give is: Perhaps. Perhaps the changing culture alone would have been enough eventually to persuade Southern legislators to repeal segregationist laws. Perhaps the changing culture alone would have been enough eventually to persuade Southern poll workers to stop using their discretionary authority to exclude black Americans from the voting booth. Perhaps it alone would have been enough eventually to convince immoral sheriffs and unlawful posse comitatus to stop lynching black Americans and civil-rights workers.REF In many places and in many ways, life was improving for many black Americans. They were, for example, becoming wealthier and professionally more successful.REF But perhaps the improvements in the conditions of daily life for black Americas owe their endurance, at least in part, to the “promptness and dispatch” with which the government enforced the act against pockets of Southern resistance.REF Or perhaps, as happened with Reconstruction, the cultural winds would have shifted once again against the equality principle, leaving it to wither on the vine. The violent riots instigated by the black-power movement, which rejected the equality principle and often resorted to violence, sparked backlash against the civil rights movement, but the backlash faded quickly.REF Perhaps the lesson that the act taught was partly responsible for its fading.

I cannot reach firm conclusions about these historical hypotheticals, but the questions they raise support my earlier claim that if one aims to pin the blame on the Civil Rights Act for the myriad cultural, political, and legal ills that the country faces today, one must carefully analyze the complex strands of causation, which includes giving credit where it is due to the act’s positive outcomes.

But insofar as the claim is that the act was not necessary to teach virtue, then my response is that thinking about the law as a teacher of virtue in terms of necessity is a mistake. If, as Aquinas says, law’s purpose is to make men moral, then it is good for the law to teach virtue whenever it can teach it effectively. It is immaterial that other things are also teaching virtue. In other words, if culture is trending toward virtue, that is no reason for the law to quit its job. There are other reasons—the pragmatic reasons that Kaveny borrows from Aquinas and Isidore—why some laws might avoid trying to teach virtue by some means. For example, if a particular law would be flouted, it should not try to teach.REF Likewise, if a law, in trying to forbid certain evil choices, would forbid certain moral ones, perhaps it too should not try to teach.REF

However, subject to those constraints, law ought to lend its authority to the wider effort to teach moral lessons, especially where, as in America, there is a constant clash between one custom that embraces natural and civil equality and another that rejects both. It is right that the law should prudentially lend its authority to the former against the latter, and that is what the Civil Rights Act of 1964 did.

Is the Civil Rights Act Still a Good Teacher?

Times have changed since 1964. If I am right that the Civil Rights Act has been a good teacher, then the American people have changed for the better because of it. And if other laws, philosophies, cultures, leaders, etc., have also been effective (if not necessarily good) teachers during the years between then and now, then the American people have changed in other ways as well. Moreover, the act itself has changed since 1964. Judicial decisions have reinterpreted parts of it, and Congress has amended parts of it. Given these developments, it could be that the act either no longer teaches a good lesson or is no longer prudentially tailored to the American people.

Some evidence supports both conclusions. Racially discriminatory language, practices, and government policies are still (and perhaps increasingly) common, although their targets are usually white and Asian Americans rather than black Americans,REF and the reigning ideology among those who control so many levers of public and private power—Antiracism—explicitly endorses race discrimination and rejects the act’s moral lesson.REF The act seems to have lost its ability to teach effectively, at least with respect to that powerful minority.REF

Usefully, the framework employed here can diagnose the cause of the act’s diminished effectiveness and can help reformers to identify changes that are needed to restore it. Each of the judicial and legislative changes in the act reduced its ability to satisfy one or more of the framework’s four criteria and therefore weakened the act’s ability to teach well. For example, the disparate-impact approach of Griggs v. Duke Power,REF United Steelworkers of America v. Weber,REF and their 1991 codification holds that to avoid liability for discriminating under Title VII, employers must sometimes discriminate.REF That makes the act’s message unclear, which causes people to misunderstand its moral teaching.REF Worse, the act now both prohibits and tolerates the same vicious action, which greatly diminishes the apparent strength of the moral lesson it teaches. Meanwhile, the changes in Title VII’s damages remedies functionally punish good and neutral actions if they might be interpreted as malicious, so the act no longer limits its lesson to a plainly wrong action.REF In other words, it no longer teaches a lesson fit for ordinary people, but instead teaches one fit for people who are more angelic than anyone can claim to be. Furthermore, the Court’s (now largely abandoned) decisions permitting race discrimination in college admissions tended to heighten tribal identification and thus to undermine rather than promote solidarity.REF

Each of these changes weakened the act with respect to one of the requirements that makes coercive laws good teachers. If they were removed, the act might yet be more effective because, once again, it would better satisfy our four requirements.

Consider the reaction to the decision in Students for Fair Admissions v. Harvard College, which forbade racial preferences in college admissions.REF The Court’s previous decisions had given schools, and only schools, an exception from the usual strictures of equal protection doctrine and the Civil Rights Act.REF Thus, the Court’s decision to reverse those precedents had no legal effect on any other sphere regulated by the act. And yet, in the wake of the decision, lawyers published endless analyses of whether the decision would limit employers’ use of certain discriminatory diversity, equity, and inclusion programs.REF Proponents of the color-blind principle found renewed zeal (and material support) after the decision and successfully used the decision to persuade federal courts to strike down racial preferences in other contexts.REF

These developments cannot be attributed to any direct legal effect of Students for Fair Admissions. They suggest, rather, a renewal of the lesson that the Civil Rights Act teaches. The Court’s decision reinvigorated the act’s ability to teach well by eliminating one of the changes that had reduced its ability to satisfy the criteria of our framework. It is reasonable to assume that similar restorations would also reinvigorate the act.

One small final point: The act continues, without question, to teach one small but uniquely powerful group of Americans well: textualist judges. Judges who believe that “only the words on the page constitute the law” will likely consider and apply the act on its own terms, rejecting invitations either to ignore the text or to impose on it a gloss that obscures its moral lesson.REF Consider again Students for Fair Admissions and Justice Neil Gorsuch’s concurring opinion.REF Upon reading the act, he concluded that its “message for these cases is unmistakable.”REF It forbids schools “from intentionally treating one person worse than another similarly situated person because of race, color, or national origin,” and “[i]t does not matter if the recipient discriminates in order to advance some further benign ‘intention’ or ‘motivation.’”REF

Textualist judges reject (consistent with the text of subsequent legislative amendments to the act) the effort by collectivists to reimagine the act as permitting, even protecting, discrimination that they believe is good. To be sure, some textualist judges already learned this lesson elsewhere. Justice Antonin Scalia, for example, learned it from the Constitution, whose universal language permits “no such thing as either a creditor or a debtor race.”REF Justice Clarence Thomas learned it from the Declaration of Independence and the Fourteenth Amendment, which together create “a moral and constitutional equivalence between laws designed to subjugate a race and those that distribute benefits on the basis of race in order to foster some current notion of equality.”REF But not every textualist has been convinced by those sources, and it is good that multiple laws teach the same good lesson.REF As collectivists continue their attempts to ignore or rewrite those laws, they will likely find textualist judges unwilling to forget what the Civil Rights Act still teaches them.

Conclusion

The Civil Rights Act of 1964 finds itself the target of conservative critics who argue that it is responsible for the many cultural, political, and legal ills that plague the United States today. The act is, its critics argue, either the cause or at least a major cause of a largely successful campaign to replace the Constitution with a new civil rights regime. Putting aside the complicated question of tracing the causal factors (philosophical, cultural, political, legal, etc.) of each identified ill and of weighing their causal effects, I have argued that the argument advanced by conservative critics cannot be complete until they have considered whether the Civil Rights Act has been a good teacher of virtue. In my view, it has been a good teacher, at least with respect to race.

GianCarlo Canaparo is a Senior Legal Fellow in the Edwin Meese III Center for Legal and Judicial Studies at The Heritage Foundation.

Authors

canaparo
GianCarlo Canaparo

Senior Legal Fellow, Edwin Meese III Center

More on This Issue

COMMENTARY 3 min read

Age Verification Is Constitutional

HERITAGE LECTURE 11 min read

Can Originalism Be Moral?