Equality and Non-Discrimination in International Human Rights Law

Report Civil Rights

Equality and Non-Discrimination in International Human Rights Law

December 31, 2020 Over an hour read Download Report
Li-ann Thio
Professor of Law, National University of Singapore

Summary

“Equality and non-discrimination” law, much of which impinges on cultural traditions and religious sensitivities, are matters warranting robust public discussion—which is preferable to invoking equality to sneak in a privileged ethic while pretending to be agnostic about the common good. Within a global setting in which fundamental value divergences are acute, it is important to recognise a global margin of appreciation in interpreting contested rights claims and protecting a range of acceptable practices to vindicate the values of pluralism, subsidiarity, and democratic will. No global body is authorised to impose a diktat over a morally charged controversy with a far-reaching social agenda, disregarding the agreement of states and national democratic processes.

Key Takeaways

Distinguishing between fundamental human rights and new rights claims not grounded in international law is needed to guard against politicization by the U.N.

“Equality and non-discrimination” are not absolute—and should not trump competing human rights and goods in order to privilege a certain ideology.

To respect principles of pluralism and the democratic will of national societies, the U.N. should not pressure them to conform to new views of sexuality.

This Special Report will examine the original understanding underlying “non-discrimination” in article 2 and associated articles of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR). It will examine how these have evolved through the expansive and contested interpretations of human rights bodies as a method of standard-setting, which has been criticized as advancing a subjective ideological agenda, and the problems this has caused when situated against the existing corpus of human rights norms. Policy recommendations are offered with a view to maintain the integrity of international human rights laws, which remains the dominant, if troubled, contemporary language of global morality.

The principle of “non-discrimination” is a key provision in the UDHR,REF serving both as a foundational principle that informed the reading of all other human rights in the UDHR—as well as a substantive right itself. Article 2 of the UDHR reads:

Everyone is entitled to all the rights and freedoms set forth in this Declaration, without distinction of any kind, such as race, colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status. Furthermore, no distinction shall be made on the basis of the political, jurisdictional or international status of the country or territory to which a person belongs, whether it be independent, trust, non-self-governing or under any other limitation of sovereignty.

During much of the UDHR drafting process, it was intertwined with “equality,” both being “two sides of the coin.REF Eventually, “non-discrimination” was disentangled from “equality” and found expression in a “strong and lean”REF article 2, which applies only to UDHR rights. The concept of “equality” took up residence under UDHR article 7, which reads: “All are equal before the law and are entitled without any discrimination to equal protection of the law. All are entitled to equal protection against any discrimination in violation of this Declaration and against any incitement to such discrimination.”

The second paragraph of article 7 of the UDHR only applies to UDHR rights, while the first prohibits “discrimination of any kind.”REF Egalitarian values permeate the other substantive articles,REF as did framing other rights in terms of “everyone” and “no one.”

Article 1 of the UDHR declares that “all human beings” as “members of the human family are “born free and equal in dignity and rights.” This supports the inherence theory of rights, without specifying any philosophical basis, whether the Judeo-Christian concept of imago Dei or humanist Kantian precepts.REF It clearly rejects racial discrimination, such as Aristotle’s view that some people were slaves by natureREF and Nazi Aryanism, which necessitated article 2.REF While earlier human rights documents addressed the “Rights of Man,”REF the UDHR was not a sexist document. Originally, article 1 read “[a]ll men,” but was later altered, through the activism of delegates Bodil Begtrup of Denmark and Hansa Mehta of India to read “[a]ll human beings.”REF Drafting debates also demonstrated a concern about the economic privileges associated with feudal orders.REF

Minority Rights Treaties as Prologue

Two primary ways the UDHR radically departed from its precursors are reflected in article 2.

Universality of Human Rights. First, it universalized the application of human rights to all persons everywhere. This is reflected in the first paragraph of article 2 that all persons are entitled to all UDHR rights “without distinction of any kind.” Previously, human rights instruments in the form of the minority treaties underwritten by the League of Nations were confined to protecting ethno-cultural minority groups in certain selected European states emerging out of the dissolution of the Austro-Hungarian empire.

This inter-war experiment held states accountable for the treatment of persons within their jurisdictions by empowering any League of Nations member to draw the League of Nations Council’s attention to a treaty infraction and by providing that treaty-related disputes could be referred to the Permanent Court of International Justice. It was believed that minority issues would be “depoliticized” by being removed from the sphere of diplomatic relations to that of “law” and impartial third-party resolution, minimizing the interference of powerful states in the internal affairs of weaker ones.

One might recognize in this mechanism of providing international accountability through a permanent monitor the infrastructural design for the modern human rights regime, although this was flawed in various aspects. It was selectively applied only to those European states like Poland or Czechoslovakia who were “beholden” to the Principal Allied Powers for their territorial gains; these states were disgruntledREF because they felt they were treated unequally in being subjected to international supervision, compared to other European states. Indeed, Switzerland was celebrated for its treatment of the “minorities question” through its focus on common political ideals shared by all citizens, distinct from the German ideology of defining political community by blood (Volkstrum).REF

The prototype of these treaties was the Polish Minority Treaty,REF in which the rights of “Polish nationals belonging to racial, religious or linguistic minorities” were recognized as “obligations of international concern.” However, while provisions like article 7 referenced the equality of “all inhabitants of Poland” under the law, the international mechanism only applied to members of minorities with grievances. While “equality and non-discrimination” found “judicial recognition”REF in these minority treaties, the UDHR applied this more broadly to individuals qua human beings, irrespective of membership in a minority group.

Territorial Status. Second, the second paragraph of article 2 affirmed that UDHR rights were to be enjoyed wherever a person lived, regardless of territorial status. The reference to “non self-governing territories”REF was designed to ensure that the UDHR included people living in colonies. This is important, considering that article 22 of the League of Nations Covenant provided for civilizationally superior states to “tutor” the “backward” people of mandated territories, as a “sacred trust of civilization” until their people were deemed ready for independence. Although mandatory powers were obliged to make annual progress reports to the Permanent Mandates Commission, to be under tutelage connoted the inferior status of a ward, not a co-equal sovereign nation. This scheme sought to mitigate the rapacity of colonialism; however, grading peoples into degrees of being “civilized” cultivated resentment. This was rejected with the advent of the peoples’ right of self-determination, which gained momentum in the 1960s, when “the subjection of peoples to alien subjugation, domination and exploitation” was declared to violate fundamental human rights.REF Notably, some of the colonial and Allied Powers long resisted the inclusion of racial-equality clauses in general instruments like the League of Nations Covenant and U.N. Charter proposed by Asian and other leadersREF for fear that this would delegitimate colonial rule or race-based immigration policies such as Australia’s “White Australia” policy.REF

Today, it is accepted that many of the non-binding UDHR standardsREF have attained the status of customary international law (CIL).REF They have also been embedded in the major human rights treaties, and their influence is evident in the ubiquity of equality and non-discrimination in constitutions globally. The general human rights corpus today is grounded on the “International Bill of Rights” consisting of the UDHR and the 1966 Covenants on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) and Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR). These covenants give expression to UDHR standards and elaborate upon them. Subsequently, topic-specific multilateral treaties dealing with the elimination of specific forms of discrimination as they relate to race, women, and disabled persons were adopted. Discrimination was also addressed in numerous non-binding declarations in relation to religious intolerance; indigenous people; and national, ethnic, cultural, religious, and linguistic minorities.REF Equality and non-discrimination also feature prominently in regional human rights instruments.REF

The Inter-American Court of Human Rights, a regional human rights courtREF declared “equality and non-discrimination” to be jus cogens. Thus, its status as a foundational human rights principle is unquestioned. However, the dynamic concept of equality, like liberty, is an open-textured term whose content is elusive. There are varied conceptions and formulations of equality and a range of grounds or personal characteristics on which basis discrimination is prohibited in law and policy, all carrying different human rights implications in terms of proscribed and prescribed conduct. REF

The Challenges of Formal Equality

Formal equality does not address the substantive content of the law but focuses on treating like alike in terms of burden and privilege. It proscribes unequal treatment of persons within the same class, while permitting treating what is unlike differently. All moral and legal arguments can be framed in the form of an argument for equality. Equality is, as Peter Westen forcefully argued,REF “an empty vessel with no substantive moral content of its own.” It is parasitic on an anterior moral standard; the bare invocation of “equality” provides no moral guidance on permissible differentiation.

Every substantive equality claimREF draws content from a particular philosophical view of equality, justice, and human flourishing, which determines what differences are relevant and warrant equal or different treatment. None of these are uncontroversial. Substantive equality has led to dissimilar treatment through positive action or methods like quotas and special rights to remove systemic barriers or stereotypes that disadvantage particular groups in terms of their participation in political and economic life. The goal may be to prevent status harms and to secure equality of result in terms of welfare and “equal respect and concern”REF in terms of equality as lifestyle for all social groups.

The question then is, as a matter of international human rights law, what is the content of “equality and non-discrimination” and who may authoritatively determine this, particularly when morally controversial issues are involved? In an age of identity politics, these principles have become staples in legal and political discourse, shifting away from common humanity by positing a privileged class and a disadvantaged class and prescribing a project of achieving “equality” between them.

From the original focus on combatting racial discrimination, various social agendas, particularly those based on sexuality issues that blur status and conduct, have been polarizing and divisive. While gaining traction amongst a coalition of U.N. experts and officials, supportive states, and non-governmental organizations, the sexuality agenda also attracts strong criticism and rejection. For example, the African Group stated at a Human Rights Council discussion on sexual orientation and gender identity (SOGI) issues that:

[W]e take strong exception to any attempt to try to distort the noble cause of fighting racism to promote and advocate specific forms of unacceptable social behaviour falling outside the scope of internationally agreed human rights norms and protection….[S]uch attempts are condescending and disoriented, as they constitute a form of imposition of cultural values on others, and undermine the very notion of human rights and their universality. REF

There is no universally accepted, univocal conception of equality and non-discrimination in a plural world. Norms must be rationally justified—not merely asserted—and enjoy broad support. Equality is not an absolute value and, in particular contests of applications, conflicts between competing rights and goods may arise. Classifications that satisfy tests such as reasonableness, necessity, or proportionalityREF may be considered legitimate in various forums in determining how much “equality” is required. Ultimately, the just interpretation and implementation of human rights requires “sensitivity to cultural diversity and the validity of other ends.”REF

Historical Intent: Underlying Philosophy and Relevant UDHR Articles

The UDHR elaborated upon the United Nations (U.N.) Charter’s commitment to “human rights and fundamental freedoms” for all “without distinction as to race, sex, language or religion.”REF This list of four prohibited categories is the only way the U.N. Charter gave content to human rights,REF aside from the “principle of equal rights and self-determination of peoples,” which refer to a collective entity. While the list of prohibited grounds expanded in subsequent texts and the jurisprudence of quasi-judicial and judicial bodies, the focus for the first 30 years of the U.N. Charter was on racial discrimination, given issues like U.S. segregationist policies, apartheid in South Africa, and the Indian caste system. REF

To ascertain what model of equality and non-discrimination is espoused, the UDHR must be read holistically, not discretely, as an integrated document.REF Articles 1 and 2 have a descriptive function in seeking to guarantee human rights through an equality paradigm applicable to all members of the human family. Article 1 speaks positively of the reason and conscience all humans share, while article 2 is framed negatively as proscription. Equality is not just a right but reinforces the very universality of rights, as everyone is a human rights beneficiary. The U.N. Charter and International Bill of RightsREF “devote more attention” to preventing discrimination than any other single category of human rights.REF Freedom from discrimination has been called “the most fundamental of the rights of man...the starting point of all other liberties” and an “indispensable element of the very notion of the rule of law.”REF

UDHR Articles 2 and 7: Fused and Later Separated

Article 2 of the UDHR principle of non-discrimination is violated when differential treatment is accorded to an individual or group on the basis of personal characteristics. Any item in article 2 can be used to interpret other UDHR articles. For example, a person cannot be barred from the article 21 right of participation in government on the basis of language.

What UDHR article 7 added to the principle of non-discrimination was positive state obligations to protect individuals from discrimination by ensuring equality before the law and the equal protection of the law, as well as protection from incitement to discrimination. REF It creates a separate right not to be discriminated against, including rights not mentioned in the UDHR.

Given the UDHR’s individual-centric orientation, there is no minority-rights clause. However, it was thought that article 2, in referencing race, color, language, and national origin would provide a “strong protective wall around membership in ethnic, cultural and linguistic minority groups.”REF These adjectives describe the only groups currently recognized as “minority groups” in international law, rejecting a more sociological approach under which any numerical minority could be considered a minority for legal purposes.REF

The UDHR’s drafting historyREF shows that article 2 shared a common origin with article 7. Originally, both were fused in a single draft provision authored by John P Humphrey,REF divided, merged again,REF and then finally found expression as two separate articles.REF Both use the prohibition against discrimination in slightly different ways.REF Rene CassinREF redressed Humphrey’s over-emphasis on non-discrimination and discounting of the accountability component of “equality before the law,”REF by fashioning a separate article with the emphasis on equality before the law, which was removed from the first sentence of draft article 2. He thought that both articles contained similar, but not identical, ideas: Article 2 was the “non-dynamic part of the equality package,”REF while what became article 7 sought to implement and translate the principle into practical reality by granting everyone legal protection against discrimination within his or her own country.REF

UDHR Article 2 lists 10 protected categories, which goes beyond the four grounds mentioned in the U.N. Charter. To combat the fascist, racist Nazi denial of equality, the Communist delegates insisted upon adopting the prohibition against discrimination as a “drafting principle” that would “deeply affect the meaning of every article they wrote.”REF Their intent was to ensure the UDHR was “a secular document,”REF acceptable to persons from all religious and non-religious persuasions. The use of terms “such as,” which preceded the list, was meant to demonstrate the exemplary rather than exhaustive nature of the list:REF “no inequality could be justified on the basis that the given distinction was not specifically mentioned in this article.”REF Nonetheless, article 2, paragraph 1 does not establish a “general rule of equality but only of equality in regard to” UDHR rights. Article 2 does not establish “the right to equal treatment as a human right, but only as a principle of the Declaration.”REF

During the drafting process before the Sub-Commission for the Prevention of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities (SCPDPM) for example, the Indian delegate, Minocheher Masani, proposed adding “color.” The last three items, “property, birth or other status,” at the end of the first paragraph of UDHR article 2 were discussed in depth.REF In particular, “other status” would seem to encompass any possible basis for distinction, although article 2 itself is confined to UDHR rights—unlike article 7, which is broader in reach, similar to article 26 of the ICCPR.

The origins of these terms are worth examining. Before the SCPDPM, Soviet Delegate Alexander Borisov proposed including “property status or national or social origin,”REF clarifying that “national origin” meant national characteristics rather than state citizenship (nationality).REF There was some contestation over including “property status,” as the U.K. and U.S. representatives thought “property” should be deleted, leaving “status,” which they considered inclusive enough.

Discussions of Property, Birth, and Other Status in the UDHR

The Soviets considered “property status” necessary as it could affect how other UDHR rights, like the equal right to education, would be enjoyed, as the poor in many countries receive no education or inferior education. The intent was to ensure equal rights for the rich and poor, regardless of economic wealth.

In a later drafting session, Ukraine representative Michael Klekovin wanted to insert the concept of soslovie (class or social status) after “property status.” While the concept was discussed, no English equivalent could be identified. The Ukrainian proposal was directed against feudal class privilege, which was determined by birth, not wealth.REF Klekovin accepted the Chinese representative PC Chang’s proposal to add the word “or other” between the words “property” and “status”, to read “property or other status.”

Soviet delegate Alexei Pavlov later proposed before the Third Committee that the word “class” be added after “property or other status,” explaining that the U.S.S.R. amendment aimed to abolish economic privileges certain groups enjoyed in feudal Europe. While Rene Cassin thought that “property or other status” covered these concerns, he supported the inclusion of “class.”

The Chairwoman of the Human Rights Commission, American First Lady Eleanor Roosevelt, observed that the Commission added the words “or other” to the original phrase “property status” to accommodate views like that of Pavlov’s.REF A small drafting committee proposed that the Russian version of article 2 should contain the world “soslovie; its literal translation in English should be “estate,” but instead, the term “birth,” rather than “class,” would be used in the English version. Thus “birth” in article 2 was designed to prohibit discrimination “on the basis of inherited legal, social and economic differences” in the enjoyment of all UDHR rights. Morsink noted that many of the drafters understood and accepted this call for “a far-reaching egalitarianism.”REF Thus, the reference to “birth” in article 2 prohibited discrimination based on socio-economic factors, distinct from the “metaphysical and moral meaning” REF of birth under article 1.REF

The importance of the specific meaning of “birth,” which was vigorously debated, was evident in criticism directed at the style committee for shifting the placement of “birth” from the end of the list (when it was associated with the later social and economic items) to the middle (when it was associated with “race, sex, language and religion”). Soviet delegate Alexander E. Bogomolov said such placement deprived “birth” of its intended meaning, rendering it ambiguous or having biological implications. Eventually, “birth” was restored to its original place and context, thereby also restoring “its original meaning of (mostly inherited) social and economic privileges.”REF In other words, the term “other status” originally was designed to address inherited economic privileges.

Post-UDHR Developments and International Human Rights Standard-Setting

In 1966, the ICCPRREF and ICESCRREF were open for ratification and entered into force in 1976. Article 2(1) of the ICCPR and Article 2(2) of the ICESCR are non-discrimination clauses under which state parties guarantee the enjoyment of covenant rights “without distinction of any kind, such as” (ICCPR) and “without discrimination of any kind as to” (ICESCR) the 10 prohibited grounds listed in article 2 UDHR.REF General Comment No. 20 of the ICESCR Committee observed the use of “other status” indicated the changing nature of discrimination over time to include grounds comparable to expressly recognized grounds. This process involves value judgements.REF

Article 2 of the covenants express the principle that “the implementation of human rights under international law is primarily a domestic matter,” reflected in the exhaustion of domestic remedies rule. International implementation “is essentially limited to the supervision of domestic measures by political, quasi-judicial or judicial organs.”REF Article 2 of the ICCPR has an “accessory character” and can only be violated in conjunction with the concrete exercise of any Covenant right which gives rise to state duties; it does not establish “independent subjective rights.”REF The covenant does not treat equality and non-discrimination as absolute values as covenant rights draw distinctions: Article 6(2) of the ICCPR prohibits imposing the death sentence on persons under 18 or pregnant women; article 25 confines rights of political participation to citizens; while article 2(3) of the ICESCR allows developing countries to distinguish between nationals and non-nationals in granting economic rights. Both covenants contain articles that specifically mention equality.REF Article 27 of the ICCPR recognizes the rights of persons belonging to ethnic, religious, or linguistic minorities to individually or communally enjoy “their own culture, to profess and practice their own religion, or to use their own language.” The adjectives qualify and identify which minority groups have rights under the covenant, and General Comment No. 23 recognizes that state parties need to undertake positive measures to ensure this right is not violated.REF These provisions make non-discrimination the “dominant single theme” in the ICCPR.REF

Like UDHR article 7, ICCPR article 26 is an autonomous right to equality that applies to rights not mentioned in the covenant.REF While “equality before the law” relates to enforcing laws, “equal protection of the law” directs the legislature not to enact discriminatory laws, and may entail a positive duty to enact special measuresREF with possible horizontal effects on others, for example, in the workplace.REF Article 26 explicitly lists grounds of prohibited discrimination by guaranteeing “all persons equal and effective protection against discrimination on any ground such as race, colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status.”REF These “especially reprehended personal criteria” run “an increased risk of a violation of the prohibition of discrimination”REF and may help to establish or disprove the reasonableness of a classification.

Article 26 of the ICCPR obliges states to take active measures against discrimination. Both ICCPR articles 2 and 26 prohibit discrimination only where distinctions are unsupported by reasonable and objective criteria REF or where there is no need to secure compelling social values. As such, determining whether there is discrimination and what is reasonable must be done on a case-by-case basis, and this “depends on subjective value judgements as well as on the respective cultural, religious and social traditions of different societies.”REF For example, a system of progressive taxation requiring people in higher income brackets to pay more taxes does not violate ICCPR article 26, serving the legitimate purpose of equitable wealth distribution.

Nonetheless, the unclear meaning and boundaries of the right of substantive equality in article 26 of the ICCPR is such that the article remains “extremely controversial” with respect to its historical background and interpretation given its “potentially great explosive force.”REF The Netherlands considered denouncing the ICCPR and re-ratifying it with a reservation to article 26 in response to a Human Rights Committee (HRC) decision relating to equality of women.REF As prevailing social views are not always determinative of what is reasonable, the question of who decides whether a rule is reasonable “may be as significant as the test for what constitutes discrimination.”REF

Within the U.N. regime, specialist human rights treaties and declarations have been adopted that expand on prohibited grounds of discrimination, including age, disability, nationality, and sexuality, and embracing a complex range of factors including identity, belief, and behavior. Some monitoring bodies have advocated controversial implementation methods, as when the HRC endorsed reverse discrimination through reserved seat quotas in elected local bodies for women and reserved elected positions for certain castes in India.REF

Unlike the 1966 covenants,REF topic-specific human rights treaties have described what “discrimination’ constitutes.”REF These treaties have expanded upon the specific obligations “equality and non-discrimination” entail,’REF such as positive action, including temporary affirmative action, to eradicate sexual stereotypes (Convention on Elimination of Discrimination Against Women [CEDAW], article 5), or to correct historical injustices. The CEDAW targets both direct and indirect discrimination. The Committee on Elimination of Racial Discrimination (CERD) condemned segregation as discrimination,REF while the CEDAW committee issued recommendations treating violence against women as systemic discrimination.REF

Discrimination is addressed through methods like education and laws criminalizing the advocacy of racial or religious hatred, as article 20 of the ICCPR requires. The Convention on Rights of Persons with Disabilities seeks to promote equal treatment when possible, while respecting the different needs of the disabled by requiring states under article 5(3) to “ensure that reasonable accommodation” is provided. These treaties recognize that adopting special measures to accelerate de facto equality do not constitute discrimination, which goes beyond viewing equality and non-discrimination as largely “last resort procedural provisions,”REF in embracing a substantive conception.

Developments and Trends: Juridical Status and Interpretive Disagreement

While there are core equality and non-discrimination provisions in primary international human rights instruments, their variable formulation and interpretation has “led” to a spectrum of different results.”REF They contain open-textured terms like “any social condition” or “other status,” catch-all clauses to potentially accommodate any distinction, and which could be abused. This gives rise to the problem of who should decide what constitutes a category of prohibited discrimination and on what basis? Typical of U.N. human rights monitoring bodies, the Human Rights Committee has found that the list of prohibited grounds under article 26 of the ICCPR was not closed and that “nationality” was covered under “other status.”REF

In one of the great controversies of our time, discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation or preference has been enlisted before domestic courts and international forums in matters relating to laws criminalizing homosexual conduct, efforts to equalize the age of consent regarding heterosexual and homosexual conduct,REF and same-sex marriage. Such issues may be characterized as a matter of public morality to be determined by elected legislatures or as implicating justiciable constitutional rights to equality or privacy. Although a constitutional right in some jurisdictions, the claim that prohibiting discrimination on the grounds of sexual orientation is an international (as opposed to regional) human right is a contested one. The suggestion that equality arguments can add “decisive weight” to complex legal debates by helping “to depoliticize issues or at least to make them more politically digestible”REF is somewhat disingenuous. This is to use equality rhetorically, in the sense that no one wants to be against “equality”—but it evades the need to justify an alternative ethic privileged under the guise of equality.

While the substantive issues concerning rights based on sexual orientation will continue to be debated globally, we must resort to the test of international legality and the doctrine of sources to ascertain whether a putative norm has acquired the status of international law (lex lata) or whether it remains a political claim/soft law (lex ferenda).

Customary Human Rights Law

In order to be recognized as a matter of customary international law, a putative norm must have both “extensive and virtually uniform”REF state practice and opinio juris, a sense of legal obligation by states as distinct from comity, tradition, or expediency.

In proving consistency of practice, the sample size cannot be selective. For example, the Singapore High Court upheld the constitutionality of a law criminalizing homosexual conduct by males, attributing no weight to jurisdictions that decriminalized homosexual conduct and the positions of international and regional organizations. What is adopted elsewhere may not be suitable in Singapore. While Canada and the United States have decriminalised homosexual conduct, other countries continue to criminalise it “such as Botswana, Malaysia, Sri Lanka, Sudan, Tanzania, Yemen and the Solomon Islands.”REF

These divergent approaches do not demonstrate the “extensive and virtually uniform” practice required for a norm to attain CIL status. Indeed, the evidence indicates that a significant number of states do not consider there to exist a binding international legal obligation to decriminalise homosexual conduct, given their retention of laws criminalising sodomy. This points to the lack of international legal status of a putative norm prohibiting the criminalisation of sodomy, which is at best lex ferenda, not lex lata.REF

Even if a CIL norm evolves with the support of most states, it may not apply to a persistent objector state.REF When a CIL norm is opposed by a state, the issue is what rank it receives within a monist or dualist municipal legal systems, whether it is superior, co-equal, or inferior to the constitution and statutes, for example. In a monist system, a CIL may be directly received as part of the national legal system and may be applied by a court for various purposes, such as to influence interpretation or to ground a cause of action.

However, the automatic reception of a CIL norm within the domestic legal system does not settle the rank a CIL norm may enjoy within a municipal system. It may carry the same or greater weight than statutes or the common law (case law). In a dualist system that emphasizes national sovereignty and self-determination, CIL is not automatically part of domestic law, but must first be incorporated into national law—such as through express judicial recognition and acceptance or a statutory enactment—in order to have legal effect. There is no uniform global approach on how international law is ranked within a domestic legal system, whether it has constitutional, statutory, or common law status,REF such that close attention must be paid to the context.

Controversial Claims Based on Sexual Orientation

While equality and non-discrimination may be a foundational human rights principle, a controversial interpretation of it involving discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation does not command universal consensus that it enjoys legal status. A global examination of national approaches demonstrates widespread dissent both within and between states and between inter-governmental organisations.

Within the U.N. regime, the creation of the controversial mandate of the U.N. Independent Expert on Protection against violence and discrimination based on sexual orientation and gender identity (SOGI) met robust resistance. In particular, the lack of clarity of the vague terms of “sexual orientation” and “gender identity,” which were not enshrined in international law, was such that member states were concerned that the mandate could not be carried out fairly.REF Political strategies to mainstream the SOGI agenda within the U.N. human rights regimes include groups of states issuing joint statements before the Human Rights Council, rather than risking defeat by introducing it as a resolution for the U.N. General Assembly to vote on. The latter may be met by counter-resolutions.REF High level U.N. bureaucratsREF actively support the SOGI agenda, and some states use the Universal Periodic Review process to draw attention to SOGI issues.REF

The Absence of Consensus Around New SOGI-Based Rights

For every Council of Europe recommendation to combat SOGI discrimination,REF there is a competing view that the attempts to add SOGI as protected categories to international treaties does not, in fact, seek equal treatment—but instead seeks special rights for a specific group of individuals united only by their sexual conduct and subjective internal sense of gender. The lack of clarity around the meaning of SOGI discrimination contributes to these concerns. In Western societies that have adopted SOGI non-discrimination laws, mere disagreement over same-sex marriage has led to state punishment of religious believers.REF

A report prepared for the Organisation of Islamic Conference (OIC) views SOGI-based claims as “the most controversial subject” pitching “traditional societies in the Muslim and most African countries as well as many of the religious communities against Western societies,” where activists are “lobbying hard” to claim SOGI “as one’s inherent human right based on individuals’ choice and consent.”REF The OIC Report underscores that Muslims hold “no specific animus against homosexual individuals”; rather, they disapprove of sexual behavior that goes against their religious beliefs.REF The report considers that special rights for so-called “sexual minorities,” which is not a legal term of art,REF are unnecessary as international human rights law has enough clear provisions to combat human rights violations, including violence and discrimination, against any person or group on any ground. The report considers that sexual orientation has no legal foundation in human rights law and that this vague term was never defined or accepted in any human rights instrument or U.N. document by the consensus of member states.

The OIC report considers that “the slanted narrative of ‘genderless marriage’ and ‘alternative form of family’” based on one’s “claim of genetically predisposed ‘sexual orientation’” as a basis of seeking “specific protective laws” is a “suicidal social experiment.”REF Islamic teachings, and indeed, mainstream Judeo-Christian teachings, do not support homosexual conduct as an identity or the norm.REF It recognises that debates about whether homosexuality is inborn and immutable or whether reparative therapy is possible for gender identity disorder are heavily politicized.REF

The OIC report supports the traditional view of marriage and family, which it considers “under assault” by those who argue marriage is based on so-called heteronormative biases or based on sex stereotypes and who seek to radically redefine it as the “union of any two persons.”REF Indeed, a person identifying as homosexual and a heterosexual person have the equal right to marry someone of the opposite sex, provided other conditions are observed, for example, age, blood relation, and not already being married. What is being demanded is not equal access to marriage as an existing good, but demands for “the transformation of that good,”REF that is, to redefine marriage.

There are, of course, human rights to which all human beings are entitled, regardless of sexual orientation or preference, such as the right to vote, to a fair trial, and equal pay for equal work. As such, each claim must be examined on its merits to see if it is based on an objective and reasonable classification. But these sharply divergent views underscore a lack of consensus about the issue of whether the emerging claims of rights based solely upon sexual orientation and gender identity constitute universal human rights.

Same-Sex Marriage and Subsidiarity in Europe

Some jurisdictions, including Western Europe, have recognized same-sex marriage based on a constitutional right to privacy or equality.REF However, the European Court of Human Rights (ECHR) in Schalk and Kopf v Austria also recognizes that states have a valid interest in legally protecting the traditional definition of marriage.REF There was little common ground between contracting states in Europe about such sensitive areas of social, political, and religious controversy, owing to the differing cultural, historical, and philosophical differences of these states. Further, the Constitutions of Poland, Bulgaria, Slovak Republic, Croatia, Slovenia and Hungary affirm marriage as a union between a man and a woman, underscoring the lack of even a regional—much less a global—consensus on whether equality and non-discrimination require the recognition of ‘same-sex marriage.’

Thus, regarding controversial issues like same-sex marriage or euthanasia,REF European states enjoy a wide margin of appreciation, with the ECHR leaving the matter to the national authorities and democratic deliberation. To act otherwise would be to “lose sight of the subsidiary nature” of the ECHR’s international enforcement machinery.REF The domestic margin of appreciation goes hand in hand with European supervision. The court has permitted restrictions on convention rights such as expressive freedoms where the domestic laws of the contracting parties lack “a uniform European conception of morals” and where the views taken by these laws as to what morals require varies both in time and place. Given that national authorities were in “direct and continuous contact with the vital forces of their countries,” the ECHR considered these state authorities were better positioned than international judges to give an opinion on “the exact content of these requirements” and the necessity of restrictions.REF

Human Rights Treaty Law

No U.N. human rights treaty explicitly prohibits discrimination on the grounds of sexual orientation, although regional treaties or some domestic constitutions have done so.REF Indeed, activists have opined there are “two particular omissions” in the UDHR: Sexual orientation and gender identity are not mentioned in article 2. Nor does article 16 explicitly establish rights for same-sex couples to marry and found a family. The issue was clearly not raised during the drafting of the UDHR in 1948 or during the drafting of the 1966 covenants.

This omission is described as “understandable” since “a new normative context around sexual orientation and transgender status has only emerged in the past 20 years.”REF While there is a growing trend of international human right bodies recognizing these, the issue remains fiercely contested. The grounds of prohibited discrimination are not closed, and attempts are being made to declare or imply a new right and park it under the apparently all-encompassing category of “other status,” or to expansively read existing rights or principle. This raises the question of what constitutes a legitimate interpretative approach in construing treaties.

If a treaty vests an adjudicatory body with powers to make binding judgements, this creates binding treaty obligations for state parties only, not for third parties.REF If the treaty declares pre-existing CIL or has the effect of crystallizing CIL at the moment of adoption or subsequently generates a CIL rule through widespread consistent state practice, the treaty norm is generally binding qua CIL norm, not qua treaty norm.REF Factors like the extensiveness of ratification, the number of reservations affect the assessment of whether such extensive consensus has been reached, pointing to the generality of a putative CIL norm.REF

In the absence of a U.N. human rights court, regional human rights courts, such as the Inter-American Court of Human Rights for example, have read “any other social condition” under article 1(1) of the American Convention on Human Rights to include “sexual orientation discrimination,” which could be limited only by “weighty reasons.”REF These decisions bind state parties in contentious cases as a treaty obligation.REF

Certain human rights bodies may have monitoring or quasi-judicial powers, but no U.N. treaty authorizes a treaty body to issue binding decisions on state parties when considering their state reports, only “concluding observations”REF and recommendations; such bodies may also issue general comments on specific treaty clauses that are hortatory, not mandatory. When optional protocols authorize individuals to send communications alleging human rights violations to a monitoring body, that treaty body may examine the communication and transmit its views with its recommendations to the concerned parties.REF They do not have judicial power to issue binding judgements or to declare law by fiat, though the interactions of these bodies with state parties may provide evidence of emerging norms.

In this dialogical process, these bodies can push an agenda through publicity, as when the HRC frequently raises sexual orientation issues in relation to criminal law, the workplace, and the lack of anti-discrimination legislation or educational programs to combat negative attitudes toward homosexuality.REF

Many human rights bodies with cosmopolitan drives have sought to promote their vision of substantive equality by expansively interpreting what equality and non-discrimination requires or by a radical interpretation of the text not contemplated by the authors of an instrument. A prominent example is when the HRC, under ICCPR articles 2 and 26, opined that sex (a biological concept) could be interpreted to encompass sexual orientation and gender identity (social constructs) in Toonen v Australia.REF The decision itself was based on the committee’s view that the right to privacy under article 17(1) of the ICCPR was violated by the Tasmanian Criminal Code criminalizing homosexual conduct. In a later decision, the HRC stated that sexual orientation was covered by the “other status” grounds of article 26, rather than as an aspect of sex.REF

To read sexual orientation into “sex” is a method that has no basis in historical intent or, indeed, the conventional method of treaty interpretation, as set out in the Vienna Convention of the Law of Treaties (VCLT).REF What the text meant to the parties collectively when they were negotiating or ratifying the treaty in question needs to be examined to see whether there was intent to include a particular implicit ground of discrimination.REF The point is to detect the parties’ intention, not to supplant them, as U.N. bureaucrats do not have legislative powers to speak for the international community—nor do U.N. monitoring bodies have determinative power to declare what the treaty means. It does not appear from any of the discussions during the 20 years between the adoption of UDHR article 2 and ICCPR articles 2 and 26 that there was any contemplation of the non-discrimination clause requiring states to repeal laws criminalizing certain forms of sexual conduct. During that time, most nations had laws against homosexual conduct and similar practices, which were considered contrary to public morality.REF

Article 31 of the VCLT provides that treaties shall be interpreted “in good faith” to ascertain the “ordinary meaning” given to treaty terms “in their context” and “in light of its object or purpose.”REF Recourse to the travaux preparatoires is permissible to confirm a reading, under VCLT article 31, unless such reading is ambiguous, obscure, or leads to a “manifestly absurd or unreasonable” result under VCLT article 32. Article 31(3) provides that any subsequent agreement or subsequent practice regarding the interpretation of the treaty may be considered. For example, if most state parties, after signing a treaty containing no express “sexual orientation discrimination” prohibition, evince a pattern of repealing laws criminalizing homosexual conduct and relate this to a need to comply with international human rights obligations, this may furnish evidence of state agreement that the treaty was meant to address and invalidate such laws. Absent such patterns, the evidence is less compelling, as when a state party attaches a declaration or reservation indicating contrary intent. Indeed, if a state repeals such legislation without reference to the need to fulfill human rights obligations, this does not provide material evidence of CIL, as reasons for amending a law may lie in political compromise and desire to please special interest groups or constituents.

There is no necessary connection between legalizing a once-criminalized practice in the name of equality, non-discrimination, and accession to a human rights treaty; what is required is a sense of legal compulsion as proof of opinio juris. State parties vary widely in their attitudes and practices toward homosexual conduct, from treating it as a right to treating it as a violation of a public good. Where legislatures genuinely object to certain conduct and are not seeking to persecute people on the basis of a “status,” there can be no consensus that a treaty with a non-discrimination guarantee should be read as prohibiting distinction on grounds of sexual orientation. Even if it is the view of the treaty-monitoring committee, these views do not bind state parties or reflect the emergence of a CIL norm, as the practice of state parties must be factored in.

Argument by Reiteration

Toonen is celebrated as a strategy for advancing the SOGI agenda in an international forum at a stage in history when the agenda had little traction before legislatures and courts, producing a decision that could be used to precipitate domestic legal changes. While the views of human rights treaty bodies are not enforceable and easier for states to ignore than legally binding judgements, it has been noted these are “widely published, and carry significant moral and persuasive authority.”REF A HRC decision influenced the Australian Parliament to enact laws rendering Tasmania’s law against homosexual conduct ineffective. There is a tendency to use quasi-judicial language to confer an aura of authority upon these bodies’ recommendations.REF Further, non-binding HRC decisions are treated like precedent, framed as asserted rules of law, and cited repeatedly by U.N. bureaucrats,REF committees,REF and even some foreign courtsREF sympathetic to expansive readings of equality, non-discrimination, and privacy rights.

Many U.N. bodies and officials later cited Toonen as though it were authoritative precedent: This is an exercise in self-validation and not an accurate assessment of state practice and opinio juris, nor is it a legitimate interpretation of a legal right. Similar to the “living tree” approach to constitutional interpretation, in which the constitution as an organic instrument is read in a “progressive” manner to adapt it to changing times, elite judges or bureaucrats are assumed to know what progressivism requires, despite difficulties because “progress is a comparative of which we have not settled the superlative.”REF This type of interpretive method discounts historical intent, precedent, and even principle, in favor of the judicial imposition of subjective political preferences as an exercise in counter-majoritarianism. It is unclear why a judge would do a better job than “majoritarian politics” in discerning what a progressive rights interpretation might be, given there is no uncontroversial theory of what minority interests deserve protection.REF

“Living tree” approaches may be endorsed in certain jurisdictions, but they also attract criticisms of judicial overreach or juristocracy. Some consider that the rule of law and separation of powers is undermined where courts operate as second legislative chambers, a role certain judiciaries assiduously reject.REF Various regional human rights courts and U.N. bureaucrats appear to favor reading human rights treaties as “living instruments,”REF—discounting historical intent—and allow their preferred value-laden interpretations to be advanced. This renders texts infinitely malleable, enlisted to serve whatever the interpreter deems a worthy cause. The strategy of reiteration is to keep repeating opinions until they achieve actual or perceived canonical status, with successive iterations relying for authority mostly upon one another. Each victory is celebrated as the acme of progressivism, and dissenting views are silenced through intimidation, shaming, and slurs.

State parties of human rights treaties do not regard comments by treaty bodies as legally binding,REF though their statements may exert political pressure and influence national courts. Hence, a wide divide may exist between state practice and the opinions of treaty bodies and U.N. personnel,REF which are neither authoritative nor persuasive. The question of how and who should interpret open-textured treaty terms boils down to one of institutional competence and propriety.

Soft-Law Instruments

Activists have invoked soft international law declarations or political documents in legal non-discrimination arguments as a political strategy to advance certain interpretations of texts or in hopes of generating CIL. While some see soft-law norms in instruments like General Assembly resolutions carrying the support of some states as evidence of an emerging trend pointing to a human rights norm, others view them as indicating the absence of opinio juris in the face of sustained opposition, thus depriving the resolution of any legal authority.REF

Private actors, describing themselves as a “distinguished groups of human rights experts” and activists, have issued non-binding documents such as the 2007 Yogyakarta Principles: Principles on the Application of International Human Rights Law in Relation to Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity (YP),REF which they characterize as representing the current state of international human rights law as it relates to SOGI issues. This document claims to draw on treaty provisions and CIL norms that deal with equality and non-discrimination in general.REF The YP were updated and extended in 2017. Efforts have been made to promote itREF and track its impact.REF

Rather than reflecting the existing state of international law, the YP introduces radical interpretations of existing and novel rights, raising the banner of preventing “discrimination” to promote a radical agenda with implications for law, family life, and sexuality. These have been challenged as “an affront to all human and especially natural rights”REFand rejected, demonstrating a failure of consensus.REF Certain YP principles threaten to truncate other human rights, such as expressive freedoms that, it argues, must not be exercised in a way that “violates the rights and freedom of persons of diverse sexual orientations and gender identities.” Demands that education be enlisted to promote respect for diverse sexual orientations or that society support gender transitioning and reassignment programs are controversial: They seek to use state power to impose moral fiats, precipitating clashes with social conservatives and those of religious conscience, particularly of the Abrahamic faiths.

The YP are not the product of government negotiation and agreement, but of a group of self-selecting experts, U.N. bureaucrats, and LGBT (Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, and Transgender) pressure groups attempting to present a radical social policy vision as binding norms. Some states have utilized it as a tool: France made an explicit reference to the YP in a Joint Statement on SOGI it sponsored issued in December 2009, although Ireland, Malta, and Poland demanded this reference be removed.REF Nonetheless, it is clear that activists will continue to rally around the YP to try shape debate around its terms, to enhance its appearance of being authoritative, and to pass off lex ferenda as lex lata.REF This, is in spite of criticisms that it constitutes a misinterpretation of the non-discrimination clauses contained in long-established human rights instruments and that sexual orientation is a vague term lacking legal foundation in any international human rights instrument and not agreed to by the general membership of the UN. Furthermore, Principle 2 of the YP seeks to elevate discrimination on grounds of SOGI to an effective trump—with no room for reasonable accommodation since equality is to be realized “whether or not the enjoyment of another human right is also affected.”REF

This is nothing short of a power grab in service of a political project, without consideration for other human rights. Yogyakarta Principles drafter Michael O’Flaherty offered a provocative view that the reference in article 3 of the ICCPR to the “equal right of men and women” to enjoy ICCPR rights gave an elevated status to the prohibition against sexual discrimination. Since he deems sex interchangeable with sexual orientation, he relied on article 3 for the radical proposition that article 3 apparently “appears to elevate the suspect nature of sexual orientation-related discrimination to a higher level than that of the other listed categories.”REF

Judicial reception towards using the YP as a guide to interpreting broad concepts like privacy and equality have been mixed. While the Nepalese Supreme Court cited YP definitions of SOGI,REF the Philippines Supreme Court held that the obligations outlined in the YP “were not reflective of the current state of international law,” had no grounding in the list of formal sources under article 38(1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice, and were not binding at international law.REF The petitioner, it argued, had not “undertaken any objective and rigorous analysis” to ascertain the “true status” of “these alleged principles of international law” which were at best, de lege ferenda, or simply “well-meaning desires.” The court observed:

[N]ot everything that society—or a certain segment of society—wants or demands is automatically a human right. This is not an arbitrary human intervention that may be added to or subtracted from at will. It is unfortunate that much of what passes for human rights today is a much broader context of needs that identifies many social desires as rights in order to further claims that international law obliges states to sanction these innovations. This has the effect of diluting real human rights and is a result of the notion that if “wants” are couched in “rights” language, then they are no longer controversial.REF

The judicial role in addressing emotionally-charged social issues in which “societal attitudes are in flux,” where even “the psychiatric and religious communities are divided in opinion,” was not to impose its own views. Rather courts should “apply the Constitution and the law,” uninfluenced by public opinion, confident in the belief that “our democracy is resilient enough to withstand vigorous debate.”REF Soft law norms may precipitate debate, but it is not a foregone conclusion that they will “harden” over time to become binding law.

Problems with New Interpretations of Equality and Non-Discrimination

In implementing human rights, much harm can be done “if not entrusted to the care of impartial, efficient and reliable institutions.”REF Within the domestic context, debates over individual rights are struggled over “through a process of public debate, informed by the opinions (rarely unanimous) of professional elites.” Authoritative institutions may revise decisions. To prevent the imposition of the diktat of an unelected, unaccountable bureaucratic elite and the politicization of human rights law, “We need to have something like that [the equivalent of domestic processes and debate] in a form suitable to the international arena.”REF

This is particularly important in relation to equality and non-discrimination, given their potential far-reaching effects in encompassing all laws and policies—even their potential horizontal application to private actors. Given the proclivity of many U.N. human rights actors to adopt expansive value-laden interpretations of this principle and to discount historical intent or general state agreement, it is important to be aware of the negative impact certain strains of substantive equality poses to freedom of public discourse, democratic will and other competing human rights and goods, contrary to the principle that human rights should be universal, indivisible, and mutually reinforcing.

Taking Seriously the Law of Sources and the Universality of Human Rights

The principle of equality and non-discrimination is central to the human rights movement,REF given that human rights are the only universal rights. However, to assert that everyone should enjoy equal rights is rhetorical, providing little guidance on how to implement and realize a human right. Because of its open-textured nature, there is a danger that equality and non-discrimination may become empty vessels to be filled with one’s preferred political philosophy or prey to political capture. This is evident in the use of non-discrimination to drive changes to law and sexuality, for example. Given the diverse conceptions of equality, this cannot be discussed in the abstract, but must be grounded in history and context. While law is not static and does change, it must be changed by legitimate processes.

In order to uphold the integrity of human rights law, a distinction must be preserved between core human rights as legal rights and contested political claims. Caution is needed against the sort of reckless activism that ignores the fact that rights have duties and that the existence of a duty “has to be established beyond pointing to the value of the right to the right-holder.”REF Attempts to use human rights terminology to legitimate a politically charged agenda will politicize human rights and devalue their currency. The legitimacy of human rights will be undermined where it acts to service the one-sided championing of liberal progressivist or fundamental libertarian values, “some of which run counter to the cardinal beliefs of various religious traditions.” To maintain credibility, human rights law must operate as the “ius gentium of our times, the common law of nations.”REF

The development and application of human rights law must adhere to general international law principles and doctrines that largely rest on state consent, mitigated by the idea that this is constrained by higher law principles drawing from the natural law/natural rights tradition. Human rights law must broadly have the support of the will of the international community as a whole, and the views of the international community of states cannot be discounted in ascertaining the juridical status and normative content of a norm. Just as human rights law does not rest in theory on majority will, neither does it turn on minority will. An unrepresentative cosmopolitan elite is not empowered to declare the law for the rest of the world as keepers of the standard of civilization as they define it. Soft-law claims should not be carelessly treated as international legal obligations. National courts and authorities have the liberty to receive or reject soft law claims since these only provide guidelines, not obligations.

It undermines the universality of human rights law to claim that a controversial putative right is a human right. All such claims must be assessed and have a basis in treaty, CIL, or possibly general principles of law that would require said right to be present in all major legal systems, common and civil law, Islamic, Buddhist, communitarian, and liberal democracies. This is important, to avoid “human rightism,”REF which confuses and conflates the categories of law and human rights ideology.

On rights claims that implicate matters of political and moral controversy, these should be debated before democratic domestic forums in order to respect the principles of national sovereignty and non-interference in internal affairs. This is distinct from the principle that established human rights are matters of international concern.

Legitimate Difference of Views and a Global Margin of Appreciation

Author Susan Marks admits that “gender and sexuality politics may well appear less global when viewed from other vantage points,”REF in which light, to see sexual orientation discrimination as a settled matter is itself a European or North American perspective. There is a legitimate difference of views in this matter, shaped by national constitutional commitments and varied theories of judicial review in relation to structuring the parameters of rights and public goods and according weight to historical intent, precedent, principles, or moral theory.

Constitutions may specify what constitutes prohibited discrimination that courts are to give effect to or may give courts counter-majoritarian checks to develop these grounds through more open-textured provisions prohibiting discrimination on enumerated and analogous grounds.REF Courts may demonstrate fidelity to the constitutional text in enforcing an explicit ground of discriminationREF or in refusing to read in an implied ground on the basis that this should be by way of constitutional amendment where this is a viable possibility. Courts develop tests of legitimate differentiation based on criteria of necessity, reasonableness, or proportionality, which are shaped by contextual factors like culture and political philosophy. Courts may take sides on contested issues, such as whether homosexuality is immutable and warrants protection by prohibiting sexual orientation discrimination, or decline to do so, according to specific conceptions of separation of powers.REF While some courts have found that laws criminalizing sodomy, which distinguish between heterosexual and homosexual conduct, can be justified on grounds of public morality, others take a contrary view. REF

In Toonen, the HRC opined that treating sodomy laws as “moral issues” for “domestic decision” would immunize state interferences with privacy.REF Former U.S. Supreme Court Justice Anthony Kennedy in Lawrence v TexasREF noted that the court’s obligation was to “define the liberty of all, not to mandate our own moral code” drawn from tradition and religious beliefs. This is disingenuous insofar as it suggests such a definition of liberty is “neutral” and does not entail imposing a moral norm.

The reality is that moral decisions are unavoidable, with one public morality norm being replaced by the liberal vision of public morality, which treats heterosexual and homosexual sexual expression and partnership as morally equivalent. The latter assumes the state is being “neutral”REF when allowing individuals to decide on their personal vision of the good, based on the meta-liberal norm of individual autonomy. The liberal theory of the good, based on consent and desire, is not neutral in espousing hedonism.REF Indeed, the enactment of “hate speech” laws to penalize speech that ostensibly promotes or incites sexual orientation discrimination brings about the re-moralized state that centralizes and deploys power to bring about a certain way of thinking about public sexual morality. This could violate other human rights like freedom of thought and religious belief, as well as stifle legitimate public debate and free speech. One man’s hate speech is another man’s political critique. Comparative analysis reveals no uniform approach.

Other courts consider public morality a legitimate legislative purpose since the state is not wholly without authority to regulate matters concerning sexual morality such as bestiality, incest, and child sex grooming; indeed, some courts appreciate that social values shape what equality requires,REF and that legislation is needed to protect the “moral ethos of society as a whole.”REF However such laws that affect privacy by criminalizing private sexual conduct are subject to tests of proportionality, necessity, and reasonable classification.REF

To merely invoke “equality” to argue against differing ages of consent for homosexual and heterosexual sex, for example, is to cynically deploy equality as “a mask for a substantive conception of the good which informs the distinctions and values at play.”REF Equality claims disguise hidden assumptions. There is a certain dishonesty, or at least inconsistency, between assertions that “decriminalization does not imply disapproval”REF (in relation to sodomy law and privacy under the ECHR) and the argument that laws criminalizing homosexual conduct have a negative health impact (in that many homosexuals will not seek medical treatment for fear of the stigma). Implicitly, the assumption is that decriminalizing sodomy will remove the stigma associated with homosexuality and encourage more homosexuals to seek medical care when society approves of or morally equates homosexuality and heterosexuality.REF Decriminalization, the removal of legal sanction, does signify or signal moral approval, which is a precursor for securing the advance of the far-reaching LGBT agenda.REF

Arguably, when a proposed human right benefits a favored class of society while diminishing the human rights of others, it should be subject to rigorous democratic debate to ascertain the implications of such a claim. A human right not to be discriminated against on the basis of sexual orientation, which implicates a contested vision of equality, should not be prematurely declared a human right in order to quarantine it from further interrogation as to whether it adheres and coheres with the existing human rights corpus.

In this respect, the ECHR in Frette v France,REF held that adoption laws that drew a distinction between would-be homosexual and heterosexual adopters were justifiable, given the diversity of national approaches to gay adoption within contracting states. This same margin of appreciation was recognized in Schalk and Kopf v AustriaREF in relation to same-sex marriage. While certain jurisdictions, as in North America, may recognize a constitutional right to same-sex marriage, this does not make it a universal human right. Even U.N. bureaucrats and human rights officials recognize there is no international human right to same-sex marriageREF drawing from equality or privacy, although they call for the legal recognition of same-sex couples and conferring upon them the same benefits traditionally married partners enjoy.REF This, however, skips over the unsettled issue of whether unisex couples should receive this legal recognition or whether homosexual partnerships are morally equivalent to traditional marriage between a man and a woman. Such matters, which impinge on cultural traditions and religious sensitivities, are matters warranting robust public discussion, which is preferable to invoking equality to sneak in a privileged ethic, while pretending to be agnostic about the good.

Within a global setting in which fundamental value divergences are more acute, it is important to recognise a global margin of appreciation in interpreting contested rights claims and protecting a range of acceptable practices to vindicate the values of pluralism, subsidiarity, and democratic will. No global body is authorised to impose a diktat over a morally charged controversy with a far-reaching social agenda such as sexual orientation as a prohibited basis of discrimination, disregarding the agreement of states and national democratic processes.REF

Clash of Rights: Sexual-Orientation Discrimination and the Assault on the Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms

Human rights co-exist in the same political space and may sometimes qualify each other. Any new human rights claim must be assessed for how it impacts other human rights and public goods. To exalt one putative human right to trump all others would be one-sided. To be fair, any emphasis on one human right over another must flow from its status as a peremptory norm and, even then, this does not preclude the need to optimize the enjoyment of all human rights.

Principles of SOGI discrimination in particular, have far-reachingREF and negative effects on public discourse—and threaten to diminish other human rights.REF This is evident in the far-reaching, intrusive demands of the SOGI discrimination agenda, set forth in documents like the YP and the reports and statements of some U.N. human rights officials that do not carry the broad support of states and the international community as a whole. These “new rights” run roughshod over established human rights with no attempt to achieve a reasonable accommodation or to give due consideration to competing human rights and public goods.REF To advance these new rights involves promoting soft-law principle in the guise of universally binding norms.

Right to Education. Demands that governments should promote tolerance and respect for diverse sexual orientations through public education programs aimed against “homophobia” and “transphobia”REF through “comprehensive sexuality education”REF violate the human right of parents to instill values in their children. The failure to allow parents to opt their children out of public education on sexual morality contrary to their convictions would violate the prior right of parents “to choose the kind of education that shall be given to their children” as proclaimed in article 26(3) of the UDHR.

There are problems, too, insofar as the contents of “sexual orientation” are vague, and not every sexual orientation warrants protection, for example, bestiality, incest, necrophilia, pedophilia, polyamory, etc., are legally prohibited or socially frowned upon.REF Where is the line to be drawn between acceptable and unacceptable sexual orientation, and who has the authority to do this?

Freedom of Religion and Expression. Expansive readings of non-discrimination on grounds like sexual orientation promotes liberty and equality for some at the expense of equality and liberty for others—particularly in relation to freedom of religion, conscience and expression, as protected under articles 18 and 19 of the UDHR.

Statement 19(d) of the YP advocates that notions of public order and public morality should not be used “in a discriminatory manner” to restrict free expression “that affirms diverse sexual orientation or gender identities.” In the same breath, statement 19(e) advocates that states ensure freedom of expression “does not violate the rights and freedoms of persons of diverse sexual orientations and gender identities.”REF This gives one sector of a community superior rights to other sectors, which is inegalitarian. Further, 19(e) of the YP is broad enough to be weaponized to shut down debate on reparative therapyREF or views questioning the assumptions of the LGBT agenda in relation to “heteronormativity,” by proclaiming views that question LGBT assumptions be hate speech or a form of psychological harm that violates “human rights.” If all that homosexualism activists demonize as heretical is hate speech subject to legal or social sanction, the pillars of a free society that human rights are supposed to support are imperiled as moral dissent is then silenced by law or bullying tactics.

Principle 21 of YP would downgrade freedom of thought, conscience and religion by declaring they cannot be invoked to justify laws denying equal protection on the basis of SOGI and requiring that religious convictions about SOGI and their expression “is not undertaken in a manner incompatible with human rights.”REF This is vague and could conceivably apply to a religious publication that states that homosexuality is a moral wrong, curbing religious speech.REF

In the face of increasing calls to SOGI diversity, intolerance is demonstrated toward viewpoint diversity and other liberties like religious freedom, as where religious believers are expected to bear the burden and costs of their own lack of conformity in relation to views of sexual morality contrary to the non-negotiable tenets of their faith.REF In various sexual orientation discrimination cases, individuals and organizations suffer detriment for adhering to their convictions supporting a more traditional sexual ethic, such as hoteliers who refused to let out rooms to homosexual couples or Roman Catholic adoption agencies who refuse to consider homosexual couples as prospective adoptive parents. If the primary principle is the best interests of the child, can it be argued that same-sex households are not in the child’s best interests or must the contrary be assumed? Although co-equal rights may qualify each other, sexual orientation discrimination may operate as a trump card, such that when no reasonable attempt is made to accommodate the conscientious objection of a registrar who refused to conduct a homosexual civil partnership ceremony, as all employees were expected to conform to the council’s conception of equality. This coerces individuals to assent to what they do not agree with, which is oppressive.REF

U.N. bureaucrats have approved the launching of national public education campaigns to “counter homophobia and transphobia,”REF where a re-moralized state would impose a publicly endorsed ethic towards sexuality. This trivializes freedom of conscience, religious freedom, and the rights of faith communities and their members to free speech and the right to engage in legitimate public debate, as a facet of the right to political participation.REF

No Trumping Human Rights. When rights compete, different weighting of the public values a right embodies takes place. When U.N. officials and bodies are one-sided in privileging only the “human rights” of one sector of the community rather than the human rights of all, this suggests a lack of objectivity. When the prohibition against discrimination on sexual-orientation grounds operates to violate or unduly truncate other human rights, this goes against the principle of treating all human rights “on the same footing and with the same emphasis.”REF This discredits the entire human rights movement.

The bias of U.N. officials is also evident in their ideological, non-scientific use of terms like “homophobia” and “transphobia,”REF which are not mental diseases (as the term phobia suggests), but are rather pejorative slurs used against those who morally dissent from the tenets of the homosexual rights agenda. To presume to intrude into freedom of thought and conscience is to endorse a brand of cultural totalitarianism, enforced by the state or private actors in the name of human rights through political correctness codes or abusing hate speech legislation to silence dissenting views. Free society is imperiled when the human right to free speech and moral dissent is given insufficient weight, threatening the values of liberty and equality that human rights law is supposed to protect.

Resistance and Divisiveness. It is not surprising that the expansive use of non-discrimination on controversial grounds of sexual orientation discrimination has caused polarization and divisiveness among members of the international community who have begun to push back: “Where there is power, there is resistance.”REF

Religious groups in particularREF who view the LGBT agenda as a threat to religious and other freedoms have begun to warn against the mainstreaming and presentation of homosexuality as a normal expression of human sexuality (as opposed to morally wrongful conduct or a gender identity disorder). This points to the clash of incommensurate values. An OIC report cautioned against efforts to use the banner of non-discrimination to promote “radical, sexual and gender agendas related to sensitive issues regarding family, family life, or sexuality.”REF It called out agencies who seek to establish “controversial and unagreed[-]upon so[-]called human rights that may compromise or undermine our religious or cultural norms.”REF In the long run, this practice in may do harm to the progressive development of international human rights law, including areas where there is hard-earned, established consensus.

Given the arguments that SOGI discrimination is an attempt to impose radical ideologies that gain little traction within national legal systems through the back door of human rights and that the equation of “sex” and “sexual orientation” is controversial, advocates should draft their own declaration or convention on LGBT rights and put it up for free and full debate and for a vote within the U.N. General Assembly and before states for them to consider ratifying such a treaty. This is preferable to piggybacking on other human rights treaties like the CEDAW or the CRC, which were designed to address other pressing matters. A sexual-orientation-specific instrument would provide the forum for LGBT activists and their state allies to put forth their concerns and demands on their own terms, so that these could be clearly understood, assessed as claims for equal or special treatment, fully and honestly debated, and accepted, rejected, or accommodated.

Recommendations

To maintain the progress in the acceptance and application of human rights globally, it is important that the human rights project not be hijacked by politicized agendas. To be credible, there must be integrity in maintaining the distinction between lex lata (law) and lex ferenda (soft law, or an emerging norm which has yet to attain legal status). Policymakers can then with confidence work to ensure the observance and protection of ‘core’ recognized human rights norms, while making arguments about emerging claims in a transparent, reason-based manner to promote their acceptance as legal obligations.

  • Policymakers should guard against the politicization of human rights by distinguishing between core human rights and contested human rights claims that are not grounded in international sources of law like treaty and CIL. The opinions of U.N. experts and bodies, while influential, are not binding.
  • Policymakers should adopt a holistic view of rights, duties and goods as reflected in article 29 of the UDHR, rather than a one-sided balancing process that privileges a certain ideology. The right of “equality and non-discrimination” is not an absolute one and should not be treated as a special trump card against competing human rights and goods. Since moral judgements are impossible to evade, the moral dimension underlying law should be part of the balancing exercise, rather than arbitrarily shutting out other visions of public morality (usually the traditional ones). Ignoring religious views in particularly will cause disquiet and damage the good the entire human rights project can do. Politicizing human rights has already elicited pushback, as human rights standards and obligations cannot be developed by ignoring an important sector of the international community.
  • Policymakers should be vocal about how it is counterproductive to attempt to create controversial new “rights” or standards by misinterpreting the International Bill of Rights and other international treaties that U.N. member states never articulated or agreed to. Such attempts devalue the currency of internationally recognized human rights.REF Aggressive lobbying by LGBT rights activists has been polarizing and divisive. Some states do not consider that action that discriminates on the basis of sexual orientation constitutes a legitimate area of human rights concernsREF and are critical of over-reaching U.N. bureaucratsREF and their illegitimate project of moral neo-colonialism in sexuality matters.

Varied conceptions of equality, different interpretive methods, and sexual orientation discrimination in national law have been invoked in ways that violate human rights. Therefore, policymakers should recognize a global margin of appreciation to respect principles of pluralism, subsidiary and the democratic will of national societies. While some jurisdictions may, for example, recognize same-sex marriage as part of privacy or equality rights, whether based on the democratic views of that society or their courts, policymakers should respect the political independence of other states by letting their societies decide what they wish their social fabric and sense of social morality to be—without external coercion, pressure, or intervention.

Conclusion

Human rights law is not made by the pronouncements of human rights experts or monitoring bodies. Though they wield considerable influence in shaping human rights discourse, they have no authority to impose a moral diktat by declaring a controversial political claim to be a legal human right.

Attempting to normalize radical interpretations of existing and established human rights norms like equality and non-discrimination through continually reiterating non-binding opinions as authoritative, complemented by aggressive lobbying, thwarts full and free debate on what should and should not be recognized as a universal human right. To shortcut the process by anointing a claim as a human right is an attempt to place the claim beyond questioning. This abuses “human rights” by using it as an illiberal trump card,REF embodying a form of moral neo-colonialism in which assertions are to be believed, not argued for and justified by appeal to the “reason and conscience” all human beings have.REF

Li-ann Thio is Professor of Law at the National University of Singapore and author of Managing Babel: The International Legal Protection of Minorities in the Twentieth Century (Boston, MA: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 2005). This paper is one in a series of essays on the natural law and natural rights foundations of internationally recognized human rights. The “First Principles of International Human Rights” essays propose reforms of the human rights movement for the increased protection of the fundamental and inalienable rights of all people.

Authors

Li-ann Thio

Professor of Law, National University of Singapore

report

Human Rights: In Our Own Hands

Jun 25, 2020 About an hour read

report

The Right to Life in International Human Rights Law

Nov 20, 2020 Over an hour read

Exclusive Offers

5 Shocking Cases of Election Fraud

Read real stories of fraudulent ballots, harvesting schemes, and more in this new eBook.

The Heritage Guide to the Constitution

Receive a clause-by-clause analysis of the Constitution with input from more than 100 scholars and legal experts.

The Real Costs of America’s Border Crisis

Learn the facts and help others understand just how bad illegal immigration is for America.